"Sense" in Being and Time
Site: | Saylor Academy |
Course: | PHIL304: Existentialism |
Book: | "Sense" in Being and Time |
Printed by: | Guest user |
Date: | Friday, 4 April 2025, 11:18 AM |
Description
This article gives an overview of Heidegger's concept of "sense". Do you agree that it's not obvious that the question of "being" should be asked in terms of the word "sense"? How might assuming that the many senses of being can actually be organized around one focal sense limit our existential understanding of being?
The Concept of "Sense" in the Seinsfrage
The novelty of Heidegger's formulation of the Seinsfrage in Being and Time consists, not in its orientation towards the sense of being in general, but rather in the way in which he understands the Seinsfrage and the path he lays out in order to answer it. Heidegger's principal thesis in Being and Time is that time constitutes the horizon for "any understanding whatsoever of being" and, therefore, that time effectively constitutes the sense of being in general (Sinn von Sein überhaupt). This means that time organizes the manifold senses of being (in both its categorial and existential determinations) by referring them back to a "general" or "focal" sense. Before one examines Heidegger's thesis that time constitutes the sense of being, however, it is important to underline the following point: it does not go without saying that the question of being should be framed in terms of the concept of "sense". Even after Heidegger defines the concept of "sense" as an existential in Being and Time, the decision to formulate the Seinsfrage in terms of the concept of sense conceals a number of suppositions, the most important being the supposition that the manifold senses of being can be organized around or referred back to a focal sense. This supposition does not depend on the thesis that the sense of being turns out to be constituted by time. The entire problem of the sense of being, and the possibility of a science devoted to this problem, arises from the elementary fact that the sense of being is manifold; being has many different senses. It is not initially clear whether these senses can be organized around a focal sense. In nearly all of his courses both before and immediately after Being and Time, Heidegger continually reminds his readers and students that being is a pollachôs legomenon (πολλαχῶς λεγόμενον). He introduces the Seinsfrage by referring to the universally recognized, even pre-philosophically available fact that being has many senses, i.e., that the understanding of being, which constitutes Dasein in its being, is as diverse and differentiated as the kinds of being that there are. Furthermore, he consistently restricts the multiplicity of the senses of being to the level of beings alone. It is beings in their diversity that differentiate the sense of being and distribute it over the whole territory of beings. Nevertheless, for Heidegger, the diversity of the senses of being is never so radical as to affect the sense of being in general. The sense of being, once determined, can account for the many senses of being, for however different these senses may be both from one another and from being itself, the focal sense of being does not evaporate in mere equivocation. Being is not equivocal, and only insofar as it is not equivocal can the question regarding its sense first arise. And yet being is not univocal either. It does not always and everywhere have the same sense. Hence the problem: if being is neither equivocal nor univocal in its sense, but rather has an Aristotelian "unity of analogy," as Heidegger put it in Being and Time, what does being mean, and how can the sense of being organize its manifold senses?
The manner in which Heidegger formulates the Seinsfrage as a question about the relation between the focal sense of being and the many senses of being in no way depends on any substantive phenomenological thesis. It is entirely Aristotelian, and can be formulated without reference to the phenomenological method or phenomenological concepts. Indeed, Heidegger sets out to demonstrate why ontology is only possible as phenomenology in Being and Time. He sets out to demonstrate why the Seinsfrage can only be raised and answered by means of phenomenology. The manner in which Heidegger formulates the Seinsfrage also does not depend on any theses about the correlation between being and time. That time constitutes the horizon for any understanding of being whatever is Heidegger's answer to the Seinsfrage, and forms no part of the formulation of the Seinsfrage, which can and has throughout the history of metaphysics been raised without any explicit reference whatever to the correlation between being and time. The correlation between being and time, as the explicit and privileged object of ontological inquiry, is peculiar to Heidegger's own project in Being and Time. Thus, I will postpone discussing the correlation between being and time until, in order to focus first on how the concept of sense operates in Heidegger's formulation of the Seinsfrage in Being and Time. My hypothesis will be that Heidegger's interpretation of time, or the way in which he understands the relation between being and time, is deeply determined by the concept of sense he employs in his formulation of the Seinsfrage. I will argue that Heidegger's strategy for motivating the Seinsfrage consistently failed to establish the thesis that being has a focal sense that can be the object of ontological inquiry. I will conclude by suggesting (but only suggesting) that Heidegger's thesis that time constitutes the sense of being is philosophically problematic and historically questionable. The Greeks (Aristotle) did not (not even unthematically) understand being in terms of time in the way that Heidegger suggests. Rather, I will argue, they understood time in terms of motion, and motion in terms of power (dunamis-energeia, δύναμις-ενέργεια), a fact Heidegger knew very well, and which he analyzed in many contexts, but which he consistently interpreted in ways that favor the priority of time (constant presence) over every other "horizon" of the understanding of being.
Source: Tarek R. Dika, https://inprjournal.pubpub.org/pub/crossing1-expositio-dika/release/3
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 License.
Is the Sense of Being Given in the Understanding of Being?
Heidegger's principal strategy for motivating the Seinsfrage – and
motivating the Seinsfrage has become absolutely necessary in light of
its forgottenness and obscurity – is to point
to the fact that we already live in and therefore have an understanding
of being. In Being and Time,
Heidegger addresses the objection that there is no need to raise the
Seinsfrage, since being "is of all concepts the one that is
self-evident," for "[whenever] one cognizes anything or makes an
assertion, whenever one comports oneself towards entities, even towards
oneself, some use is made of 'being' […]. [In] any way of comporting
oneself to entities as entities – even in any being towards entities as
entities – there lies a priori an enigma. The very fact that we already
live in an understanding of being [Daß wir je schon in einem
Seinsversändnis leben] and that the sense of being is still veiled in
darkness proves that it is necessary in principle to raise this question
again". From the fact that we live in or have an
understanding of being (and, therefore, of beings in their totality),
Heidegger infers that there must be a sense whose sovereignty over the
many senses of being can be demonstrated. This sense remains "veiled in
darkness". The thesis that the sense of being is veiled in darkness
depends on the thesis (1) that there is such a sense, and (2) that the
many senses of being somehow veil its focal sense. But has Heidegger
actually demonstrated that the understanding of being depends on the
prior givenness of the sense of being? Not at all. From the fact that
Dasein lives in the understanding of being, it only follows that Dasein
understands the many senses of being, not that these senses are
organized around or refer back to a focal sense, which each of the many
senses differentiates in its own way.
In Being and Time,
Heidegger once more insists on the fact that Dasein's understanding of
being indicates that the sense of being has already been disclosed to
it, if only in a vague, average manner. He first insists that "we always conduct our activities
in an understanding of being. Out of this understanding arise both the
explicit question of the sense of being and the tendency that leads us
towards its conception. We do not know what 'being' means. But even if
we ask, 'What is 'Being'? we keep within an understanding of the 'is,'
though we are unable to fix conceptually what that 'is' signifies. We do
not even know the horizon in terms of which that meaning is to be
grasped and fixed. But this vague average understanding of Being is
still a Fact". Here,
Heidegger claims that the question of the sense of being merely renders
explicit the understanding of being itself. The Seinsfrage is simply
what the understanding of being becomes when the latter turns towards
itself and raises questions about its content and possibility in order
to discover the sense of being that underlies and determines it. The
sense of being – i.e., the Erfragte, the third and most important part
of the formal structure of the question of being –
unassumingly "falls out" of the understanding of being when the latter
adopts the comportment (Verhalten) of ontological inquiry.
Later Heidegger once more insists on the givenness of the sense
of being in the understanding of being: "Everything we talk about,
everything we have in view, everything towards which we comport
ourselves in any way, is being; what we are is being, and so is how we
are. being lies in the fact that something is, and in its being as it
is; in Reality; in presence-at-hand; in subsistence; in validity; in
Dasein; in the 'es gibt". In this passage,
Heidegger has effectively enumerated many of the senses of being he
hopes to ground in the focal sense: being as reality (presence-at-hand),
as existence (in the traditional sense, existentia); essence (also in
the traditional sense, esssentia); Dasein (Existenz); truth. There is no
contesting the fact that Dasein understands all of these senses of
being. Nevertheless, once more, Heidegger has inferred from the fact
that Dasein has an understanding of all of these senses of being that
there is a focal sense each of these senses only declines or
differentiates. All of his descriptions of Dasein's understanding of
being presuppose that this understanding would not be possible without
the prior givenness of the (conceptually obscure, but nevertheless
effective) focal sense of being, which binds these senses to one another
and so exercises ontological priority over them all.
From
these considerations, I draw a preliminary conclusion: the introduction
to Being and Time does not conclusively demonstrate that the Seinsfrage
can only be formulated as a Frage nach dem Sinn von Sein, because the
only possible basis for such a thesis is not itself demonstrated: viz.,
that the sense of being is given in, and so informs the understanding of
being, such that the latter would not be possible without the former.
The dependence of the understanding of being on the sense of being is
presupposed, but not demonstrated. Heidegger's descriptions of the
understanding of being phenomenologically yield only that Dasein
understands the many senses of being, not that this understanding
depends on the prior givenness of the focal sense of being. The only
remaining way for Heidegger to demonstrate the thesis that the sense of
being achieves givenness in, and so informs the understanding of being
is to demonstrate it, not independently of the thesis that the sense of
being is constituted by time (as it should have been demonstrated), but
rather precisely by reference to this thesis alone, which is not
demonstrated by the end of this unfinished treatise, not even by
Heidegger's own admission. Henceforth, in
order to show that being has a focal sense that determines its manifold
senses, Heidegger must show that the focal sense is time, and he must
show how time organizes and distributes the many senses of being.
Heidegger must demonstrate in the conclusion what he could only
presuppose in the introduction. This is not a circularity charge, which
Heidegger adroitly disposes of early on in the introduction by oblique
reference to Plato's Meno and Aristotle's Posterior Analytics. Clearly, in a very general sense, in every inquiry, the object of
inquiry must in some way already be given. I am not criticizing
Heidegger for claiming both that we already know what being means and
claiming that we have yet to discover what being means. I am claiming
that Heidegger does not demonstrate the prior givenness of the sense of
being in the understanding of being. In other words, Heidegger does not
satisfy the phenomenological criterion of evidence. On the contrary, he
infers the prior givenness of the sense of being from what is truly and
alone given: the many senses of being, of which Dasein does indeed have
an understanding. This understanding is given, very clearly. Heidegger's
thesis that the understanding of being depends on the prior givenness
of the sense of being stems from traditional (Aristotelian) ontology,
not phenomenology. That Heidegger must demonstrate, and cannot simply
assume, that the Seinsfrage can only be posed by distinguishing between
the focal sense of being and the many senses of beings is clear: his
entire aim in the introduction to Being and Time is to pose the
Seinsfrage and to remind his readers of what the question means, to
reawaken the Seinsfrage in his readers precisely as a question of sense.
Sense, Horizon, and Time
I
claimed that Heidegger does not successfully (i.e., phenomenologically)
demonstrate that the Seinsfrage must be formulated in terms of the
focal sense of being, as contrasted with the many senses of being. There
is, however, a further supposition Heidegger makes in his formulation
of the Seinsfrage that cannot be passed over here: viz., that the sense
of being, whatever it might be, can only be determined by reference to
the "horizon" in terms of which beings are understood. The concept of
the "horizon" is transcendental, and denotes an a priori condition of
possibility (not in the Kantian, formal sense, but rather in the
phenomenological, concrete sense of a condition that can itself be
exhibited in phenomenological intuition and, therefore, evidence). An
horizon gives light to whatever appears within its limits (peras), and
here, what appears within its limits are beings. The thesis that the
sense of being can only be determined by reference to an horizon is
logically independent of the thesis that the horizon is time, however
closely related these two theses are to one another in the conceptual
economy of Being and Time (so closely related that we hardly ever
distinguish between them). That the sense of being must be determined in
terms of a horizon only means that, whatever the sense of being might
be, it can only appear in the light cast by a transcendental condition.
To assert that time is the horizon in which any understanding of being
moves is to assert that it occupies the office of such a condition, and
as such enjoys priority over being as the foundation of its sense (and,
therefore, as what enables us to fix its sense). Thus, before Heidegger
has even attempted to offer an interpretation of time, he has already
assigned it a definite place in ontological inquiry: viz., that of a
condition. Furthermore, because of the equivalence between (1) time as
the horizon of the sense of being and (2) time as the horizon of
Dasein's understanding of being, the next steps of the inquiry have been
clearly delineated: it must be shown that time conditions Dasein's
understanding of being. An existential analytic therefore becomes
necessary. The concept of horizon interposes time between being and
beings, such that beings understandingly appear to Dasein only insofar
as they are temporally projected by Dasein via what Heidegger terms its
"potentiality-for-being" (Seinkönnen; pouvoir-être). If (1) the
Seinsfrage is formulated in terms of the focal, unified sense of being,
which commands the totality of its many senses, and if, moreover, (2)
this sense of being can only be disclosed, not via a definition of any
sort, but rather as an horizon, and if, finally, (3) the horizon is
itself defined as time, then it is only by way of Dasein's deployment of
temporality in thrown projection that the sense of being can be
disclosed. In this way of posing the Seinsfrage, time enjoys
transcendental priority over being, so much so that fundamental ontology
becomes reducible to "temporal science," where time is interpreted in
an explicitly transcendental manner, due to the form of the Seinsfrage
and, more specifically, the dependence of the sense of being on its
horizon.
But Dasein is an entity whose sense is itself
dependent on the prior givenness of the sense of being. Claude Romano
has compellingly demonstrated that Heidegger's project in Being and Time
and Basic Problems of Phenomenology fails because his analysis of
Dasein's temporality ultimately yields only three senses of being, none
of which can be identified with the sense of being in general. These
three senses are Zuhandenheit, Vorhandenheit, and Existenz. The first
two depend on the ecstasis of the present and its modification in the
now (Gegenwart, Jetzt), and the third depends on the ecstasis of the
authentic future (Zukunft). The problem is that these three ecstases,
together with their corresponding schemata, do not in any way seem to
converge in or disclose a focal sense, but are rather irreducibly
diverse, so much so that they render the sense of being equivocal.
Heidegger's interpretation of time does not establish the focal sense of
being, but only mutually irreducible senses of being. To be sure, all
of these senses refer to or are based on time, but they are mutually
irreducible senses of different entities, and do not disclose a focal
sense that encompasses them all. I agree with Romano's interpretation,
which further confirms not only that Heidegger does not demonstrate in
the introduction to Being and Time that the sense of being is given in
and determines the understanding of being (and so can become an object
of ontological inquiry), but also that he has not demonstrated this by
the end of Being and Time and Basic Problems of Phenomenology, which
contains "a new elaboration of Division 3 of Part 1 of Being and Time,"
where Heidegger intended to finally disclose the sense of being in light
of the horizon of time. Heidegger's recognition of this failure led
him to realize that his formulation of the Seinsfrage stemmed, not from
die Sache selbst, but rather from the one aspect of the history of
ontology that survived the otherwise radical Destruktion he carries out
in Being and Time: the formulation of the Seinsfrage as a question about
the sense of being, to which all other senses can be referred and in
which they find their unitary ground. In the 1930s, Heidegger will
abandon the project of trying to account for the sense of being by way
of time. He will abandon the concept of "sense" in his formulation of
the Seinsfrage. In the Kehre, he will focus on the co-belonging of Being and Time in the Ereignis, without prioritizing one over the other,
according to a decidedly post-transcendental Fragestellung hinting in
the direction of a phenomenology of givenness.
Being, Time, and Power
Instead of
following Heidegger down the path of the Ereignis, however, I would like
to briefly pursue the suggestion I made. I have already explained
why Heidegger's thesis in Being and Time that time constitutes the
sense of being is philosophically problematic. I would now like to
explain why it is also historically problematic. The Greeks (Aristotle),
I suggested, did not (not even implicitly) understand being in terms of
time in the way that Heidegger suggests. Rather, they understood time
in terms of motion, and motion in terms of power (dunamis-energeia,
δύναμις-ενέργεια), a fact Heidegger knew very well, and which he
analyzed in many contexts, but which he consistently interpreted in ways
that favor the priority of time (constant presence) over every other
"horizon" of the understanding of being. Why did Heidegger insist on
the primacy of time as the unthematized foundation of ontological
reflection in the West since Aristotle, if not earlier? In Heidegger's
texts, it is clear that this historical thesis rests on his
interpretation of the basic categories of Aristotelian ontology. The
basic thesis running through all of Heidegger's interpretations of
Aristotle is that the fundamental concepts of Aristotelian ontology are
only intelligible in light of time (and, more specifically, the
privilege Aristotle gives to constant presence in his interpretation of
being). He frequently contends that Aristotle, together with the
subsequent history of ontology up to Hegel, failed, for essential
reasons, to fully appreciate the dependence of being on time, and so
could not pose the Seinsfrage in the way in which, he felt, it had to be
posed: viz., in terms of the relation between being and time.
Heidegger's presentation of these theses is extremely abbreviated in
Being and Time, but it can be found in a more elaborated form in
texts written both before and after. One of the clearest formulations
can be found in On the Essence of Human Freedom (1930), where Heidegger
examines the concepts of ousia, parousia, eidos, energeia, and finally
aletheia. He interprets all of these Aristotelian concepts in terms of
time and, more importantly, in terms of constant presence, and he
regards his temporal interpretation of Aristotelian concepts as evidence
for his own thesis that being has always been understood in terms of
time, even and perhaps especially when the relation between being and
time is not explicitly stated as such or even remotely understood.
It is important to remember that Heidegger does not simply regard his
interpretation of Aristotle as a merely "external" confirmation of an
independently, phenomenologically verifiable thesis about the relation
between being and time. On the contrary, as he himself explicitly
asserts: "If this interpretation of being as constant presence
[beständige Anwesenheit] is not correct, there can be no basis for
unfolding a connection between being and time, as demanded by the
fundamental question". Nevertheless, things are not so clear.
Heidegger wavers. Immediately after, he continues: "Yet although Greek
metaphysics as such, together with the subsequent tradition of Western
metaphysics, is of great significance for our problem, its implications
do not extend this far. For even if for some reason or other our
interpretation of Greek ontology could not be carried through, what we
have asserted as the fundamental orientation of the understanding of
being could be exhibited from our own immediate comportment towards
beings […] as will be shown – we humans must understand being in terms
of time". Here, Heidegger insists on the fundamental exteriority of
any historical investigation vis-à-vis the correlation between being and
time, which can, he claims, always be demonstrated independently by
reference to the understanding of being, and so remain secure from
history, should any "anomaly" in the history of being creep in and
destabilize the required correlation between being and time Heidegger
demands. Clearly, Heidegger is worried about the possibility that his
analysis might not yield the required conclusion: that the history of
ontology, beginning with the Greeks, has always understood being in
terms of time. But he is too subtle to simply reverse his earlier
statement, for he adds yet another fold: "However, the history of
metaphysics provides us with more than just examples. […] [History]
offers us more than a picture of earlier and superseded stages of
thought. […] If we try to grasp the Greek concept of being, this is not a
matter of acquiring external historical knowledge," for it helps us
show that the Greek concept of being has determined the history of
ontology up to Hegel in a non-arbitrary way.
How should we
interpret Heidegger's hesitations? He is not seeking in history a series
of "examples". Indeed, Dasein's understanding of being must always live
itself out in terms of time, and the interpretation of historical texts
must always confirm this. Any historical exception is no longer a mere
exception, but rather constitutes an objection to the philosophical
thesis that Dasein always understands being in terms of time. In other
words, Dasein's Seinsverständnis places constraints on the
interpretations of being historical Dasein has produced from the Greeks
to the present. Suppose, then, that Heidegger were to demonstrate what
we now know he cannot: viz., that the focal sense of being is
constituted in the horizon of time and that this sense organizes all
other possible senses of being. What would happen if Heidegger's
interpretation of Aristotle were to turn out not to confirm the thesis
that being is always interpreted in terms of time? Would we say that
this is a mere anomaly? An exception that proves the rule? Not at all.
We would say that such a "disconfirmation" should be a priori
impossible, given the kind of being that Dasein is and the fact that the
history of ontology is but the history of various attempts to
articulate what its understanding of being consists in. The trace of
time as the foundation of the sense of being must leave its mark in
every understanding of being whatever, from the most ancient to the most
contemporary, and from the most vulgar to the most elevated. This trace
can never fully be erased, however buried it might be.
Significantly, Heidegger's hesitations about the importance of the
history of ontology in confirming his thesis that being has always been
interpreted in terms of time occur immediately after the section of the
course devoted to the concept of energeia. Regarding the latter, he
writes: "In summary, we can say that the Aristotelian concept for the
actuality of the actual, i.e. the concept of energeia as well as the
later concept of actualitas, determined by this, does not initially
confirm our thesis of 'constant presence' as the fundamental meaning of
Being in Greek philosophy". Why? This is not immediately clear. On the
contrary, everything in Heidegger's text up to this point seems to
suggest that his interpretation of energeia does confirm the thesis that
constant presence is the fundamental meaning of being in Aristotle.
After all, Aristotle himself, as Heidegger interprets him, correlates
dunamis to apousia and energeia to parousia in the conceptual economy of
metabolé, which is the essence of phusis, and which Heidegger's regards
as fundamental to Aristotle's concept of ousia
metabolé (μεταβολή)
apousia (απουσία) parousia (παρουσία)
dunamis (δύναμις) energeia (ενέργεια)
Why, then, if energeia belongs to parousia, can there be any risk of a
disconfirmation in Heidegger's fundamental thesis that being has always
been interpreted in terms of time? Here, I can only risk the following
hypothesis: because the play of dunamis and energeia grounds the play of
apousia and parousia (i.e., of ousia as defined by these two terms),
rather than the other way around, because dunamis and energeia are more
fundamental, since they ground time itself. Time is but the measure of
change, and the play of dunamis and energeia are the source of all
change in phusis. Time reveals itself as secondary, derivative, by
comparison to dunamis and energeia, for these do not depend on time,
rather time depends on them. The value of presence in Aristotle is but
the value of fully manifested power in energeia. No manifest power, no
presence. Energeia does not occur "in the present," it is itself the
source of any and all presencing. The word energeia denotes the
manifestation of a dunamis, of an ability-to-be. In short, energeia is
the manifestation of a Seinkönnen, which is also the origin of Dasein's
temporality. Dasein does not project into a future that is already
there, but rather in projecting its own potentiality-for-being is the
future. Even in Being and Time, power has priority over time, since time
arises directly from Dasein's ability-to-be. Heidegger's reduction of
energeia to parousia in On the Essence of Human Freedom is a strategic
decision made in the interest of preserving the correlation between
being and time, for in truth parousia is reducible to energeia. But if
this is so, then we must raise questions about Heidegger's temporal
interpretation of the fundamental concepts of Aristotelian ontology, and
perhaps invert the order of priority:
metabolé (μεταβολή)
dunamis (δύναμις) energeia (ενέργεια)
apousia (απουσία) parousia (παρουσία)
To conclude, I have defended two theses, one "historical," and one
"philosophical," although the distinction between them cannot be
rigorously maintained in this context. The "philosophical" thesis is
twofold. First, Heidegger demonstrates neither that the sense of being
is given in the understanding of being in the introduction to Being and
Time nor that time constitutes the horizon of the sense of being by the
end of Being and Time and Basic Problems of Phenomenology. Second, power
determines Heidegger's own interpretation of the understanding of being
even in Being and Time itself: Dasein always understands itself in
terms of its ownmost ability-to-be, and time is nothing over and above
this ability-to-be, in all of the various ways (authentic and
inauthentic) in which it can be modalized. The "historical" thesis is
that Aristotle did not interpret being in terms of time. Ousia is
reducible to energeia as the manifestation of dunamis, and time, despite
its importance, is secondary. The concept of the phenomenon in
Aristotle, and perhaps beyond, is essentially the concept of expressed
power. These two theses reorient the concept of the phenomenon and the
question of being in a different direction, towards the concept of
power, and away from the concept of time.
Is There a Body without Flesh?
In this paper I investigate the theme of sense and nonsense as it
pertains to the phenomenological problem of "flesh". My remarks here
also respond to the two-fold, intellectual invitation Emmanuel Falque
has extended to philosophy to embark into theological territory and to
engage without polemic or fear in a combat amoureux over the things that
matter - the things themselves. Struggle can be loving only if the work
itself is motivated by a love, and a love of what we can still dare to
call truth. It is in this same spirit, which I recognize and esteem in
Falque, that I wish to address here the question of body and flesh that
is central to his work, as it is for many others.
I will
raise two main sets of questions that have been the subject of
historical debate, and Falque knows them well, because they are also his
questions: 1) How should we describe and understand the relationship of
flesh [Leib] to body [Körper] and body to flesh? Can we give legitimate
status to the materiality of the corporeal condition while maintaining
the phenomenological privilege of flesh and life? Or, alternatively,
should we deny the privilege of flesh in favor of a more moderate
"balance" of flesh and body, and so rescue material embodiment from the
oblivion to which a naive priority of flesh would consign it? 2) By
extension, how should we describe and understand the relationship of
flesh and body, in their phenomenality, to the theological reality of
the Incarnation of the Word? How is the passage into theology effected
in phenomenology when it is a question of body and flesh?
In
a way that has not yet been acknowledged adequately, these questions
bear on the relationship of phenomenology and the sciences, which also
deal with "bodies," perhaps exclusively and with greater rigor than
phenomenology. What do we gain from recognizing this bearing? It is
explicitly against what he perceives to be rampant Western materialism
and its unilateral science that Michel Henry frames the phenomenology of
life. It is also in the name of material, embodied reality that Falque
objects to Henry's approach. For reasons I will spell out in detail, and
while I recognize his theological hesitations and share his theological
commitments, I think Falque's objections misconstrue Henry's position.
We have good reason to doubt that the phenomenality of incarnation, in
either its philosophical or theological senses, can be adequately
described by a phenomenology in which perception is ultimate.
The Myth of Experience
Is there a body
without flesh? The question seems as rhetorical as the inverse one
Falque poses to Henry. We already know Henry's answer: A body cannot
appear, and thus be, unless it is first given to flesh. This rule
applies whether I am dealing with a material body in the world or with
the corps propre, my own body. In the one case as in the other, a body
cannot appear unless it is first given to sensibility, and nothing is
given to the senses I call mine unless it affects me. Apart from this
affective instance, without a flesh that is impressional, I have no way
of saying whether I am dealing with the front of a thing or its
backside, its blue hue or hardness, girth or speed, or with its
disappearance, because I know nothing about it. I can offer no
description, phenomenological or otherwise. Of what would it be the
description? I have no access to a thing unless it is given to me in
experience, or in imagination, as composed of what is so given. Unless
I can be affected, unless I am endowed with flesh, nothing like a body
can appear and I am simply not entitled to speak of a body, not even as
an idea.
Why then ask whether there is a body without flesh
if such a possibility for these decisive reasons is unintelligible? Can
any further precision show the question to be worth the annoyance of
posing and the labor of investigating? What is a body and what is flesh?
According to the standard definition, a body in general is a material
thing bearing sensible or intelligible properties - the categories of
Aristotle (time, change, motion, quality, size, place, etc.), or the
sensible qualities of Galileo or Descartes (extension, figure, etc.),
the pure forms of intuition of Kant (space and time), or the properties
of sub-atomic physics (spin, location, charge, mass, etc.). Even in the
latter cases, where the properties of a body are not known through the
senses, but through instruments of measurement that have been designed
to detect and record what the senses cannot, senses nevertheless must
intervene to "read" such instruments. The physicist that denies that our
senses tell us the truth of the universe must consult the senses in
some way in order to arrive at that conclusion.
The
question can nevertheless be answered affirmatively. Yes, there is a
body without flesh. The universe is populated with bodies of this sort,
which are what they are independently of any appeal to flesh for their
appearance. First, for the strict reason that they do not appear to
flesh and do not affect it directly. In itself, flesh knows nothing
about them. Second, because they are what they are, and will be what
they will be, whatever we may wish to assert about flesh, or even if we
wish to ignore flesh, and what is given to it, altogether. It is not
even obvious that someone must observe the Large Hadron Collider, since
programs can be designed for that purpose, and register the events in
question with more subtlety and precision than the "naked eye". If we
were smart enough, we would program those computers also to interpret
the data better than we can, find errors in our assumptions, mistakes in
our models, and so on. From this perspective, not only is there a body
without flesh, perhaps an infinite number of them; in addition, if we
are to arrive at the truth of the bodies that populate the universe, we
must ignore flesh altogether.
Including our own? Nothing
prohibits the positive sciences from applying the same methods to the
human body they apply to the cosmos. Whether we are dealing with cell
biology, genetics, neuroscience, or the other cognitive sciences, no
reference to flesh is required, and it is not obvious how any discussion
of flesh, in Henry's sense, can be included in either the assumptions,
methods, or results of these fields. It is true that some forms of
cognitive research on so-called "live" subjects do involve prompting the
subject of research to "think about" or "imagine" an object, and so
forth. Through a process of trial and error, it is possible to correlate
material events in the brain with reported experiences, so that
eventually consciousness would be, as Daniel Dennett says,
"explained". What seems to be, and is called, an experience of
something, is in fact, caused or occasioned by material episodes of
which we are entirely unaware. Edit the episode (or what codes for it),
edit the experience. Even if some are uncomfortable with the idea of
dismissing human experience as entirely illusory, the scientific
position is clear: the material, bodily event is phenomenal; the
experience of sensing and of sensed, scientifically speaking at least,
is epiphenomenal, or worse, illusory.
If such a conclusion
seems difficult to accept, resolving it goes beyond the purview of
science. Let politicians, therapists, pharmaceutical companies, social
workers, school teachers, and prison guards deal with the consequences.
Science must tell us only what is true. We must dare, precisely not to
think anymore, but to experiment. It is no longer the philosopher who
dethrones the gods of the mythmakers, but the scientist; and in the
universe of science, only one god is worthy of the name. Evidence. But
the etymology of the word is no longer its meaning. If e-videre means to
come from seeing, here in question is not seeing, nor even what is
seen, at least if that must involve and depend upon sensibility. Rather,
a certain way of determining and "explaining" the material world,
including what we do see, that is the arche and telos of science, the
limits of its veritas and its realitas. Is the ambition of science
anything but to establish once and for all a correct explanatory account
of the universe in all its dimensions on the basis of an exact
understanding of the causal relationships that govern its constituent
parts?
In any case, we are up against a problem. We have in
phenomenology a reference to flesh and to the sensing body as a
necessary condition of experience and definition of reality, and the
exclusion of any such reference in the natural sciences, as a condition
of any experimentation and also as a definition of reality. How should
one respond intellectually or practically to this
apparently-unresolvable dilemma cutting the history of reason in two? On
the one hand, the world of our experience, with all its sensible
delight - our ambitions, aims, and hopes, fears and regrets, joys and
sorrows, love and hate - this world of meaning, of sense, of value. On
the other, the empirically-observable, material world of bodies visible
to us, or detectable in dimensions far beyond what we can see - this
material world, the better understanding of which continues to benefit
humanity in myriad ways.
An objection arises: Where is the
dilemma? If the visible universe is an element, and a marvelous element,
of the world of experience, as of creation, then no rational person
ought to resist the desire to understand the mechanisms by which it
operates. Can one really suppose it to be a world of inert bodies in
which no meaning, no sense, can be found? The apparent contradiction
between sense and nonsense - here, the world of meaning and the world of
senseless bodies - covers over another one that is more difficult. We
are up against two incompatible definitions of the real. If so-called
"first-person" experience cannot be reduced, and what is observed in the
third-person can never be raised to the level of experiencing itself,
for what kind of correlation can we hope?
Embodied Mind: Thinking Matter
The opposition
just posited - between the world of meaning, on the one hand, and the
world of senseless, inert bodies, on the other - is it artificial or
contrived? Far from being a contradiction needing resolution, are these
worlds not already, originally and always, conjoined, as Merleau-Ponty
has taught us? Flesh is a body that is part - a body-part - of this
great body that is the universe (we leave aside the question of whether
another, or an infinite number of others, is possible). Flesh, the
living, sensing body, is a constituent part of the universe, even if it
has raised itself - but why "raised"? - to the level of self-awareness.
Admitting the worldly nature of flesh does not require us to nullify or
diminish the realm of meaning, the so-called "space" of reasons.
"Meaning is not a mysterious gift from outside nature," John McDowell
reminds us; to think so would commit us to a "rampant platonism".
Cognition, and the mind as such, is "embodied". In its acts of knowing
it need neither be absorbed by nor separated from what it knows, but is
or at least can be "simply present and available".
In
significant continuity with Merleau-Ponty's work, a growing field of
research now seeks to demonstrate the thesis that the fleshly body is a
worldly body, and to do so while respecting the prerogatives of both
phenomenology and science. To take one notable example, Evan Thompson
in Mind in Life aims to integrate phenomenology and cognitive science in
an "enactive" approach that promises to describe and explain at once:
"Starting from a recognition of the transcendental and hence
ineliminable status of experience, the aim would be to search for
morphodynamical principles that can both integrate the orders of matter,
life, and mind, and account for the originality of each order". Once a
dynamic morphology of sufficient complexity is recognized - made
possible by new topologies, differential geometry, etc. - it is possible
to "map," and then to demonstrate, dynamic and isomorphic relations
that arise between physiological systems and perceptual forms.
The effort to achieve such a demonstration, Thompson thinks, would have
been embraced by Merleau-Ponty, had a morphology of sufficient richness
and complexity been available to him. From this perspective, the remove
at which classical phenomenology stands vis-à-vis science, emblematic
of Husserl's Krisis (to say nothing of Heidegger's position), is not a
matter of principle, but only a contingent, conceptual constraint,
bounded as it was by the limits of the sciences then-available. In any
case, if Husserl thinks it is the task of phenomenology to assign the
sciences their ultimate meaning, it cannot accomplish this task unless a
genuine connection arises between phenomenology and the sciences it
purports to ground. Otherwise, phenomenology amounts to little more than
a series of one-sided assertions and pronouncements about the world of
experience, which the world of science can safely ignore. But if the
results of the sciences can be altered by taking into account
phenomenological insight, as advocates of this approach have shown, then
the sciences cannot afford to ignore it.
How should we
account for this development phenomenologically? How is it possible that
a phenomenological analysis according to the strict phenomenological
reduction of what is given in intuition, far from providing the antidote
to materialism, naturalism, or reductionism, is now enriched by it, to
the point of morphing into a "naturalized phenomenology"? We should
not fail to notice that protagonists of the enactive approach refuse
"objectivism" quite explicitly, and insist on the irreducible,
transcendental character of "experience" as the condition for the
possibility of the appearance of any object. In addition, and this point
is perhaps more important, we are not dealing with a conflation of
methods or perspectives, since the engagement with science goes hand in
hand with and is predicated upon the insistence on the importance and
irreducibility of the phenomenological perspective. One might reasonably
consider such an approach to offer a kind of concrete synthesis of mind
and world, rather than the a priori one Kant sought.
If the
world of experience is irreducible to the world of science and yet
integrated with it, is that not what we ought to expect and indicative
of a certain correctness? Or, alternatively, in order to effect such an
integration of phenomenology and science, has the concept of experience,
necessarily, become a concept of scientific experience alone? Or, yet
again, are we dealing with a Malebranchean parallelism that is simply
harder to detect because the lines now overlap, or intertwine, to use
Merleau-Ponty's word? What is involved in the reduction of experience to
scientific experience (that is, the experience of the scientist) and
what are its consequences? I will offer three objections, which will
lead us into a more refined and direct engagement with the question of
flesh and its relation to the body before opening onto a theological
question.
First, properly speaking, I do not and cannot have
an experience of my neurons as objects. It is true that I can connect my
own scull, let us call it le crâne propre, to a brain scanner, and vary
my thinking as I watch correlating parts of my brain light up on a
screen. On the basis of such correlations between my thought and my
body, can I ever claim to have an (original) experience of my neurons as
sensible or intellectual objects? It would be a reflective experience,
and nothing would keep me from learning something perceptually about my
body in this way. But what I observe on the screen is not my body and
can never be, at least if by body we mean the original, subjective body
in its original givenness to itself, its auto-affection, or
pre-reflective awareness.
Second, if what I observe is not my
body, but only a visual representation, can we say that the correlation
has proved successful, that we have evidence for it? Even if one
embraces the brilliant level of engagement of phenomenology with
science, even if one were to achieve the perfect accord of carnal
affectivity with the perception of the body, the problem of principle
remains: these are two irreducible orders of givenness, of
phenomenality. A fundamental practical problem also remains: Imagine a
real-time projection of every dynamic alteration of the organic body
flashed on a optic lens, available to the concrete perception of my eye -
visible. Is it even possible to perceive, organically, the immense
complex that is the organic body, all in one view?
A third
and parallel objection can also be raised. The possibility of such a
perception is highly-specific, and more often than not, prohibitively
expensive. What is given in it goes well beyond what is given in the
range of perceptual experience available to anyone. If the notion of
what is phenomenal - and, even more, its phenomenality - however
broadened and enriched, is available only to one who has already entered
into the scientific perspective, and if such a perspective excludes in
principle the subject that perceives, feels, or enjoys, then such an
approach can indeed admit perception, feeling, or enjoyment, but only on
the condition that they become what they are not, which is to say,
reports of a perception, feeling, or enjoyment. The problem is not that
such reports can be mistaken, which in any case might prove relevant for
the experiment, but rather that, in the phenomenality of such a report,
the original phenomenon is torn from its original givenness, apart from
the world, in order to disclose it in a visibility that is foreign to
it. Yes, the scientist engrossed practically in an experiment, or
theoretically in the effort to design or modify a model for what is
observed experimentally, also perceives - that is, sees through forms,
however rarified they may be. But experience has here been reduced to
scientific experience. It can be extended to the universal - taken as
universal experience - only by a decision.
If many suspect
the world of science and with it virtual reality, automation, and
so-called artificial intelligence have encroached too far, it is because
the lifeworld as living has been colonized by technology. That is why
those who adopt it, who prefer to experience the world or themselves as
mediated by technology, risk losing knowledge of the world or
themselves apart from it. "The information age will be the age of
idiots," claims Henry in 1987. The orgasm-feigning robot that will
cater to your every wish, or discipline you as programmed, perhaps when
you least expect it - or can it learn that you expect that? - is indeed a
body without flesh. "Life is but a motion of the limbs… why may we not
say , that all Automata… have an artificiall life?"
Touching Flesh: Sensing Nonsense
In light of
Michel Henry's phenomenology of life and its critique of scientism, such
a decision stands out in all clarity, but in order to admit it must we
follow his characterization of flesh as originally auto-impressional?
For Henry, the reality of flesh is invisible, irreducibly and in
principle. In its original givenness, where it is given to itself as
auto-impressional and the only place its givenness is original, it does
not and cannot appear in the exteriority of world. Nor can flesh be
extended to the world in the manner of Merleau-Ponty's touching-touched,
sensing-sensed, feeling-felt chiasm. Endowed with a power the world
forever lacks, the hand that is touched, when it is a question of one's
own body, can become the hand that touches. That is correct. But the
in-principle reversibility of touching and touched that characterizes
the living body does not extend to the material world. No coffee cup
"touches" the hand that holds it, nor has a stone ever picked up the
hand that throws it. The ontological duplicity that distinguishes
phenomenologically the body of flesh from the worldly body seems
unassailable.
But have we lost the body in its worldly
reality in the process? Emmanuel Falque thinks so. In his view,
Henry's thesis concerning auto-affection, and originary flesh as
auto-impressionality, fails to account for anything like the body, or
the embodied condition as we actually experience it, in "flesh and
bone," as he says: "[N]othing indicates, beyond his masterful
descriptive analyses, that there is a genuine access to the body through
the flesh. Put otherwise, everything happens as if the flesh, that is
to say the experience of our own life, becomes so invasive here that we
would come to forget that it is possessed and even experienced, at least
materially and visibly, in and through a body". For Falque, the flesh
that is ours is not only seeing but also visible. It can indeed be seen
and touched. This visibility is not simply one way of access to flesh,
and to flesh that is ours, but the first way of access. We experience
and possess flesh also through our body; and there is no flesh, for us,
that we cannot also see or touch.
Falque and Henry thus offer
two quite distinct conceptions of flesh that seem incompatible. For
Falque, Henry's flesh "disincorporates," "absorbs," and ultimately
"destroys" the body, and with it all the "thickness" of what is felt.
After all, "it is also necessary to recognize the weight of our own body
(and its kilos, we dare to say!) without which this pain [of a steep
climb, for example] would never be experienced" (157). What
phenomenological reality would such a pain have, if not for the fact of
the body's quite material weight, which does not simply explain or
measure the pain at a causal level, as the reference to kilos might
suggest, but is also involved in the very fact and event of it? Falque
certainly must have the phenomenality of weight in mind, precisely its
heaviness, and not only the relative scientific measure of a primary
quality.
On the other hand, there is no question that in
Henry's approach only an auto-impressional flesh can experience its own
heaviness or lightness. I feel the weight of another not perceptually,
by seeing it, but only and at most when the other (the other's weight)
is quite strictly bearing down upon me. But even in this case, I do not
feel the weight of the other, properly speaking - that is, its heaviness
for the other, which remains strictly invisible (an object not of
sensibility, but impressionality). Its impressional status does not make
it inhuman. Quite the contrary. For Henry, the heaviness or lightness
of flesh can be felt only because it is capable of feeling itself, and a
worldly body - the strict concept we all have in mind when we speak of a
worldly body - is not so capable, even if it can be assigned a weight
value. For Falque, heaviness or lightness can be felt only by a flesh
that also weighs something, and thus also bears the properties of a
worldly body. Otherwise, how can we say that is its own heaviness? I
think such a question motivates Falque's objections. The phenomenology
of incorporation, and not only of incarnation, has its own legitimacy,
but seems impossible if the phenomenological distinction of flesh is not
first admitted. Of course, we can question whether kilos, to use one of
Falque's examples, is an essential characteristic of the body, or only
of its relation to the earth. The physicist will speak of gravity, but
not flesh, and nothing keeps gravity from serving as a total principle
of explanation in a so-called "unified theory".
In Henry's
perspective, I do not experience the "weight" of my body, which strictly
speaking is an abstract measure. Rather, I experience, as a resisting
continuum, the resistance of the body I am; and I experience fatigue in
my effort to overcome it. A worldly body, from this angle, experiences
no such resistance or fatigue, but friction and entropy. Moreover, the
fatigue of my flesh is not fatigue at a distance, but my own proper
exhaustion. If the weight of my flesh is felt, it is felt because my
flesh feels it in itself, not because it senses it at a distance, as a
sensed body. I can always form the intention of the object "weight,"
assign it to my body, which I also see, and appeal to my perception of
the weight and the body to gather these two distinct objects together in
a unity. But no fatigue is felt in such a perception, since fatigue is
affective. I feel the fatigue, before I have a perception of it, and
whether or not the thought of it ever crosses my mind. That is why, for
Henry, the flesh is auto-impressional, without any reference to the
sensed body.
In my own view, though I do not pretend to have
fully demonstrated it here, I think Henry's position is necessary if
Falque is to have what he wants, which is the body in its visible,
material, incorporated reality - and to have this together with flesh -
in a way that also supports a genuinely theological conception of
incarnation and incorporation. Moreover, I think Falque gets a deeper
version of what he wants if he embraces Henry's perspective, for only
what transpires in flesh can account phenomenologically for what we
"observe" in the living body, not only the phenomena of birth and growth
in the mundane sense, but also of distress, sorrow or joy, which do not
register visibly in the body at random, but account phenomenologically
for, indeed explain, what so registers (the lines of distress in a face,
tears of joy upon seeing a loved one, etc.).
Eyes of Faith: Flesh of the Theological
These questions as far as they go remain phenomenological and do not
depend upon articles of faith. Nevertheless, Falque correctly detects in
Henry's Incarnation a liaison between Part II and Part III, between the
phenomenology of flesh stricto sensu, and Incarnation in "the Christian
sense". Here, Falque advances a second principle objection and a
positive claim: "[N]othing ensures, at least in reading Michel Henry's
work, that the divine incarnation in a flesh pure and simple
[Inkarnation] also expresses the becoming human of God [Menschwerdung]…
Only a theology of the body or of the purely organic, rather than a
unilateral phenomenology of the flesh, will be able to produce the
identification, frequently avoided by Michel Henry, between the carnal
incarnation of God and his historical and corporeal humanization in the
figure of the incarnate Word".
Falque seems to suspect that
Henry subsumes "Incarnation in the Christian Sense" under a general and
also inadequate phenomenology of incarnation. Far from providing an
account of incarnation in the Christian sense, Henry's phenomenology of
life glosses over it and renders it equivalent to the fleshly condition
of anyone. At best, Revelation becomes a mere moment of phenomenology,
rather than the absolute Transcendent. What is worse, it can hardly be
called "incarnate" or even "human," since it is fundamentally
dis-incorporated. Flesh without body, in this precise sense, is finally a
gnostic flesh, as a-corporal as a-cosmic. It is neither Christian nor
human. "A monadism and a modalism of the Henryan flesh would thus become
all the more dis-incorporated as the body would be destroyed and
absorbed into it".
In response to this precise objection,
let us consider more closely a text that Falque cites in support of
these claims and that seems to invite the charge of Spinozism. Henry
describes the living person [vivant] as "no more than a mode of it
[auto-impressionality]. In other words, it is something that has no
consistency by itself, but only as a manifestation, modification, or
peripeteia of a reality that is other than it". Read one way (as
Falque reads it), this passage seems to deny the integrity of creation,
and to assert a strange, if not to say false, relation with an a-cosmic,
unworldly, dis-incorporated reality. One cannot even say it is a
relation of dependence, which would already imply a consistency of its
own, but rather a relation that merely, as Spinoza might say, expresses
the absolute. If Henry means what Falque thinks he means here, Falque
would be right to reject it. But I think Henry is saying something else
entirely, and a better understanding of it will also shed light on
Falque's other objections.
I read Henry's phrase, "has no
consistency by itself," with Augustine rather than Spinoza in mind. If
Henry means that apart from Life and, in a deeper sense, apart from
God's own life given in Christ, human living dis-integrates, and lacks
unity or consistency, then Henry's claim is impeccably
phenomenologically and theologically precise. Neither here nor elsewhere
does Henry turn finite flesh into a dis-incorporate epiphenomenon
lacking all reality. Nor does he claim it is only a "mode" of absolute
life in the manner of Spinoza. Henry is claiming, instead, at least
three things: 1) Finite flesh is not autonomous absolutely. The pretense
to be itself on its own, by its own power, is illusory. It cannot
give itself its own law if it cannot give itself its own life. 2) Flesh
can be a site in which life manifests itself, or alternatively can be a
site where life is denatured. Whether one or the other eventuality
ensues is, in part, a function of the kind of relation flesh maintains
with the life that gives it to itself. 3) Infinite Life, strictly
speaking - insofar as it brings itself about in itself [se porte
soi-même en soi] - is, with respect to finite life, an alterity, "a
reality that is other than it".
Here we have a fundamental
distinction between finite and infinite flesh, an alterity not reducible
to the alterity of the finite other. It expresses in phenomenological
terms what the creature-creator distinction expresses theologically. As
fundamental as it is, however, that distinction does not destroy the
fundamental relation that is creation. But Falque does not see this
distinction in Henry, or does not find it strong enough: "There is a
distance in the relation of the human to God… that is not identical to
the distance of sin". For Henry, once again, finite life cannot "bring
itself about in itself". The power to give life, even life to itself - a
power at infinite remove from any human power - it forever lacks. I am
not "my own" life and will never be. Is this not, in fact, the orthodox
concept of creation? God is Life and the giver of life, and all the
living bear a relation to God by virtue of their living condition.
It is not simply creation that Falque finds missing, but also an
orthodox concept of incarnation. Somewhat surprisingly, he suspects that
Henry denies that the Son of God has taken on the human condition in
every way but sin. Where Henry writes that the "one who took on flesh in
Christ was not an ordinary man but the Word of God" (160 / 69, Falque's
emphasis, citing Incarnation, 231 / 331), Falque interprets Henry as
denying that Jesus was born in human likeness, just like any of us, with
a carnal body of visible matter. But here again nothing prohibits us
from reading this differently. The one who has taken on human likeness
in the man Jesus is not just anyone, is not you or me, but rather the
One who is in himself the Word. Of course Jesus is a man like any other,
but he is not only a man like any other, since he is in his person the
very Word of God. Falque wants to compliment an emphasis on the
"exemplary" with an emphasis on "the ordinary life and common fleshly
humanity of the Son of God".
In addition to an adequate
conception of the humanity of Jesus, it is also the uniqueness or
singularity of the incarnation that Falque wishes to safeguard. Now
citing "the philosopher" Merleau-Ponty: "the Incarnation changes
everything". And Falque is right. Incarnation in the Christian sense
does change everything. But Falque thinks incarnation in Henry's sense,
like the astral flesh of Marcion, or the angelic flesh of Jakob Böhme,
cannot "change" anything, strictly speaking. How could it if the
auto-impressional flesh it involves is forever a-temporal, invisible,
dis-incorporated, and thus entirely unlike the temporal, visible, bodily
appearance of the Word made flesh, which in the words of John, "we have
heard… we have seen with our eyes… we have looked at and touched with
our hands"? If we are to affirm these words, as we do, must we not
side with Falque against Henry on this point? The theology Falque wishes
to preserve is not in question here, but only the phenomenology, and
thus the conditions under which (the way) the revelation of God in
Christ comes to manifestation.
How does the affirmation that
the Word was made flesh in a flesh like ours go together
phenomenologically with the theological singularity of the Word made
flesh, indeed its primacy? For as we have seen, it is not just any
incarnation in question, in your flesh or mine, but the incarnation of
the One who is the Word. To be more precise, how must we describe,
following Nicholas of Cusa but this time phenomenologically, the
co-incidence of the following two apparently-irreconcilable opposites:
The man Jesus is both seen and heard, and rejected as God by many? Can
a phenomenology that starts with visible body tout court do it? We
should avoid any hasty appeal to faith to explain the difference between
acceptance and rejection. Falque's intuitions are correct: it is not
only the eyes of faith that see God in Jesus, but the sensible eyes of
the body, and also the intellectual "eyes" of those who contemplate him.
But by insisting that the one who sees Jesus - i.e. sees him "bodily" -
does indeed perceive God in the flesh, has Falque left any room for
those who wish to deny it, as many did and still do? After all, they do
not reject what they see, a man in space and time, visible like any
other. Nor is it a different man, but the same one his followers also
see. What they reject is that this appearing man is God. (In this
precise respect Falque claims about the priority of the body are
correct. In the order of historical time, they see Jesus first, before
some come to believe he is the Christ). But can the humanity of
precisely the Word made flesh be recognized as such by appealing first
or exclusively to the visibility of it, where the meaning of "flesh" is
blended with, and finally phenomenal as, the visible body? How then
could we come to terms with the invisibility of the Father? In the
Johannine text, Jesus says: "No one can come to me unless drawn by the
Father who sent me… Everyone who has heard and learned from the Father
comes to me. Not that anyone has seen the Father except the one who is
from God; he has seen the Father".
By refusing the
phenomenological privilege of invisible, auto-impressional flesh, not
just the experience of flesh or life, but flesh as it undergoes
experiencing itself - is Falque committed to an exclusivism of the
sensed? Not necessarily. He does not refuse the fact of an invisible
dimension of flesh, but refuses it priority, and refuses to sever its
(visible) bond with the irreducibly visible, the "spread body". He
refuses the notion that flesh is invisible alone, sensing alone,
touching alone, in favor of a view that it is also, and at the same
time, visible, sensed, and touched - which is to say, is also body. Of
course, at one level, Falque's claims are entirely legitimate. This
"thing" I call my flesh "is" also this "thing" I call my body. The
distinctions Henry and others make between the subjective body, the
living body, the organic body, the objective body, and so on, these are
phenomenological declinations of the body as such. The body, as such,
"is" their unity. But only in flesh and as flesh is that unity
self-given. It is not given in its original phenomenality either in
perception or in sensibility.
If we wish to follow
Merleau-Ponty's path, as Falque does, either we must remain in an ontic
register that denies the fundamental, original, phenomenological
irreducibility of visible and invisible, world and life, and finally
flesh and Life, or we must enter into theological territory and with
eyes of faith recognize these twos as ones. One can offer a kind of
phenomenology from faith, as Emmanuel Falque does so well, but one can
also wonder whether, because this is a phenomenology of faith and from
the perspective of faith, it is theology more from "from above" than
"from below," despite everything. "Eyes of faith" here means, minimally,
hearing the Words of Christ and believing, and maximally, participating
fully in sacramental life. If we remain in the realm of sense
perception and confine our understanding of these realities to the sheer
ontic unities of flesh and body, body and world, flesh and world, we
seem committed to a theologically- and phenomenologically-questionable
materialism. If, instead, we understand seeing as seeing in the light of
faith, we must admit that it is faith that gives the incarnate unity in
question, Word and flesh, and Word made flesh. In the order of
perception, it is faith and not sensibility, or better faith with
sensibility, that gives the unity in question. The one who denies that
Jesus is Lord also sees Jesus, or could do so. In seeing Jesus they also
see the Lord, and deny him. But they do not deny what they see, Jesus.
Without the duplicity of appearing, one has either a kind of ontic
phenomenality, so to speak, or faith. But then he phenomenality of
faith, properly speaking, would seem to remain out of reach, since the
sensible has already, of itself, been so fully loaded with faith. It is a
way of thinking the unity of faith and phenomenological reason, but
perhaps one that risks compromising something of both. The theologian
must still bear the burden of describing phenomenologically what life
means, and what it means for that Word to give its life for the world,
for you and for me, what it means to live with it and in it and from it,
to "participate" in precisely that Life and no other, and to be made
able to do so. I am not confident all this can be done on the basis of
the phenomenality of the world alone. Of course, I understand "world"
here in Henry's sense and not that of Merleau-Ponty, and an objection to
the position I am sketching here might find in that fact a point of
dispute.
The charges of Gnosticism and Spinozism, in any
case, are misapplied and ultimately unhelpful, at least when it comes to
what clearly becomes the trajectory of Henry's final writings on
Christianity. Like Kierkegaard says life must be lived, Henry's writings
on Christianity must be read forward, but can only be understood
backward. Life does not save me from the world, nor do I need saving
from it. It simply gives itself otherwise and differently than what the
world gives and how the world gives. The givenness of the world (as much
as of the body and its bones) is and remains a givenness, but never a
self-givenness. This is a phenomenological claim, not a soteriological
one. The two should not be confused. But the decision to limit one's
understanding or definition of reality to the unilateral exteriority of
the world may indeed have soteriological implications. We may never come
to terms with what faith means, what faith is about - to say nothing of
creation, which is not a mere concept but also reality itself - if we
remain so limited.
* * *
A word remains to be said
about the engagement of phenomenology with science and its place in
these reflections. That area of study has its own merit, legitimacy, and
interest. The protagonists of such research deserve enormous praise,
with two small qualifications. First, the effort to correlate first- and
third-person perspectives risks slipping to a kind of scientism if only
those correlations ground the phenomenality and phenomenological
legitimacy of experiencing undergoing itself in flesh. The phenomena
arising in flesh are proper to flesh. The varying worldly vestiges of
it, including its practical action, illuminate only what a world can be
(including the world of science). They do not give or illuminate or
justify what is given in flesh in itself, which has its own
phenomenological integrity. Secondly, and for a related reason, science
will never prove God (and here we mean "science" and not "reason"). Nor
will it ever prove, for example, that Jesus is Lord. "If they do not
listen to Moses and the prophets, neither will they be convinced even if
someone rises from the dead". None of this can count in any way as a
failure of science, but only as a difference from phenomenology, and in
another way, a difference from faith.
Falque's phenomenology
of flesh and bone is clearly distinct from Henry's phenomenology of
life, and the distinctions between them merit further investigation. I
share the same theological commitments as Falque, and I hold in high
regard the profound spirit of his theological vision. These objections
are only about phenomenology, and in a secondary way about how
phenomenology relates to Christian faith, tactically speaking. I suspect
that ultimately Falque's objections to Henry presuppose that one has
already refused Henry's basic theses concerning phenomenality and the
duplicity of appearing. But new questions can also now be posed, this
time to Falque: Does the phenomenological priority of the body to the
flesh assume a theological acceptation of the body as sacramental, and
thus as theologically meaningful, as significant? If so, should we not
understand this to be a sacramental phenomenology? And if that is the
case, does it presuppose and depend upon the eyes of faith, or even
sacramental experience, for its phenomenality? In my view, the further
development of the phenomenology of life may also go in a sacramental
direction. Henry himself invites it, and it is not clear that a
rapprochement between their positions could not be found there.
In any case, one cannot avoid being struck by the subtle moments Falque
expresses thanks for the reprieve that arrives when Henry admits a kind
of "transcendent" life. But Falque does not put much stock in it. Why?
Because admitting it, he thinks, would make of Henry's work a total
contradiction and destroy its most important theses. But I think Falque
and with him almost all readers of Henry have missed something very
important. The phenomenology of life Henry finds in Christianity is not
reducible to his own. Henry discovers in Christianity a depth (of life)
that offers more than his own phenomenology on its own can provide, a
depth which later involves a reproach that overturns the entire
affective economy and the world of ethics it presupposes. If we must
turn to Words of Christ to see its contours and extent, nothing
prohibits us from reading Henry's final text, in part, as a response to
Falque's objections. If that is in any way the fruit of a combat
amoureux, for this we can also thank Emmanuel Falque.