Rounding Out Arguments
Site: | Saylor Academy |
Course: | PHIL102: Introduction to Critical Thinking and Logic |
Book: | Rounding Out Arguments |
Printed by: | Guest user |
Date: | Tuesday, 8 April 2025, 9:17 AM |
Description
Read these sections to learn how to round out arguments conceptually. The first section will distinguish between two types of argument: deductive and inductive. Pay careful attention to the difference between these two, and think about which kind of argument you use more often. The second section will help you identify arguments with a missing premise and determine how and when to supply this missing premise. It will also introduce you to the principle of charity and the difference between normative and descriptive statements – three very important terms! The third section shows you three rhetorical devices to hint at further argument without actually going through the argument: assuring, guarding, and discounting.
Complete the exercises, then check your answers against the keys.
Deductive vs. Inductive arguments
The concepts of validity and soundness that we have introduced apply only to the class of what are called "deductive arguments". A deductive argument is an argument whose conclusion is supposed to follow from its premises with absolute certainty, thus leaving no possibility that the conclusion doesn't follow from the premises. For a deductive argument to fail to do this is for it to fail as a deductive argument. In contrast, an inductive argument is an argument whose conclusion is supposed to follow from its premises with a high level of probability, which means that although it is possible that the conclusion doesn't follow from its premises, it is unlikely that this is the case. Here is an example of an inductive argument:
Tweets is a healthy, normally functioning bird and since most healthy,
normally functioning birds fly, Tweets probably flies.
Notice that the conclusion, Tweets probably flies, contains the word "probably".
This is a clear indicator that the argument is supposed to be inductive, not
deductive. Here is the argument in standard form:
- Tweets is a healthy, normally functioning bird
- Most healthy, normally functioning birds fly
- Therefore, Tweets probably flies
Given the information provided by the premises, the conclusion does seem to
be well supported. That is, the premises do give us a strong reason for
accepting the conclusion. This is true even though we can imagine a scenario in
which the premises are true and yet the conclusion is false. For example,
suppose that we added the following premise:
Tweets is 6 ft tall and can run 30 mph.
Were we to add that premise, the conclusion would no longer be supported by
the premises, since any bird that is 6 ft tall and can run 30 mph, is not a kind of
bird that can fly. That information leads us to believe that Tweets is an ostrich or
emu, which are not kinds of birds that can fly. As this example shows, inductive
arguments are defeasible arguments since by adding further information or
premises to the argument, we can overturn (defeat) the verdict that the
conclusion is well-supported by the premises. Inductive arguments whose
premises give us a strong, even if defeasible, reason for accepting the
conclusion are called, unsurprisingly, strong inductive arguments. In contrast,
an inductive argument that does not provide a strong reason for accepting the
conclusion are called weak inductive arguments.
Whereas strong inductive arguments are defeasible, valid deductive arguments aren't. Suppose that instead of saying that most birds fly, premise 2 said that all birds fly.
- Tweets is a healthy, normally function bird.
- All healthy, normally functioning birds can fly.
- Therefore, Tweets can fly.
This is a valid argument and since it is a valid argument, there are no further
premises that we could add that could overturn the argument's validity. (True,
premise 2 is false, but as we've seen that is irrelevant to determining whether an
argument is valid). Even if we were to add the premise that Tweets is 6 ft tall
and can run 30 mph, it doesn't overturn the validity of the argument. As soon as
we use the universal generalization, "all healthy, normally function birds can
fly," then when we assume that premise is true and add that Tweets is a healthy,
normally functioning bird, it has to follow from those premises that Tweets can
fly. This is true even if we add that Tweets is 6 ft tall because then what we have
to imagine (in applying our informal test of validity) is a world in which all birds,
including those that are 6 ft tall and can run 30 mph, can fly.
Although inductive arguments are an important class of argument that are commonly used every day in many contexts, logic texts tend not to spend as much time with them since we have no agreed upon standard of evaluating them. In contrast, there is an agreed upon standard of evaluation of deductive arguments. We have already seen what that is; it is the concept of validity. In chapter 2 we will learn some precise, formal methods of evaluating deductive arguments. There are no such agreed upon formal methods of evaluation for inductive arguments. This is an area of ongoing research in philosophy. In chapter 3 we will revisit inductive arguments and consider some ways to evaluate inductive arguments.
Source: Matthew J. Van Cleave
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 License.
Arguments with missing premises
Quite often, an argument will not explicitly state a premise that we can see is
needed in order for the argument to be valid. In such a case, we can supply the
premise(s) needed in order so make the argument valid. Making missing
premises explicit is a central part of reconstructing arguments in standard form.
We have already dealt in part with this in the section on paraphrasing, but now
that we have introduced the concept of validity, we have a useful tool for
knowing when to supply missing premises in our reconstruction of an argument.
In some cases, the missing premise will be fairly obvious, as in the following:
Gary is a convicted sex-offender, so Gary is not allowed to work with
children.
The premise and conclusion of this argument are straightforward:
- Gary is a convicted sex-offender
- Therefore, Gary is not allowed to work with children (from
1) However, as stated, the argument is invalid. (Before reading on, see if you can
provide a counterexample for this argument. That is, come up with an imaginary
scenario in which the premise is true and yet the conclusion is false.) Here is just
one counterexample (there could be many): Gary is a convicted sex-offender but
the country in which he lives does not restrict convicted sex-offenders from
working with children. I don't know whether there are any such countries,
although I suspect there are (and it doesn't matter for the purpose of validity
whether there are or aren't). In any case, it seems clear that this argument is
relying upon a premise that isn't explicitly stated. We can and should state that
premise explicitly in our reconstruction of the standard form argument. But
what is the argument's missing premise? The obvious one is that no sex-
offenders are allowed to work with children, but we could also use a weaker
statement like this one:
Where Gary lives, no convicted sex-offenders are allowed to work with
children.
It should be obvious why this is a "weaker" statement. It is weaker because it is
not so universal in scope, which means that it is easier for the statement to be
made true. By relativizing the statement that sex-offenders are not allowed to
work with children to the place where Gary lives, we leave open the possibility
that other places in the world don't have this same restriction. So even if there
are other places in the world where convicted sex-offenders are allowed to work
with children, our statements could still be true since in this place (the place
where Gary lives) they aren't. (For more on strong and weak statements, see
section 1.10). So here is the argument in standard form:
- Gary is a convicted sex-offender.
- Where Gary lives, no convicted sex-offenders are allowed to work with
children.
- Therefore, Gary is not allowed to work with children. (from 1-2)
This argument is now valid: there is no way for the conclusion to be false,
assuming the truth of the premises. This was a fairly simple example where the
missing premise needed to make the argument valid was relatively easy to see.
As we can see from this example, a missing premise is a premise that the
argument needs in order to be as strong as possible. Typically, this means
supplying the statement(s) that are needed to make the argument valid. But in
addition to making the argument valid, we want to make the argument
plausible. This is called "the principle of charity". The principle of charity
states that when reconstructing an argument, you should try to make that
argument (whether inductive or deductive) as strong as possible. When it
comes to supplying missing premises, this means supplying the most plausible
premises needed in order to make the argument either valid (for deductive
arguments) or inductively strong (for inductive arguments).
Although in the last example figuring out the missing premise was relatively easy
to do, it is not always so easy. Here is an argument whose missing premises are
not as easy to determine:
Since children who are raised by gay couples often have psychological
and emotional problems, the state should discourage gay couples from
raising children.
The conclusion of this argument, that the state should not allow gay marriage, is
apparently supported by a single premise, which should be recognizable from
the occurrence of the premise indicator, "since". Thus, our initial reconstruction
of the standard form argument looks like this:
- Children who are raised by gay couples often have psychological and
emotional problems.
- Therefore, the state should discourage gay couples from raising
children.
However, as it stands, this argument is invalid because it depends on certain
missing premises. The conclusion of this argument is a normative statement -
a statement about whether something ought to be true, relative to some
standard of evaluation. Normative statements can be contrasted with
descriptive statements, which are simply factual claims about what is true. For
example, "Russia does not allow gay couples to raise children" is a descriptive
statement. That is, it is simply a claim about what is in fact the case in Russia
today. In contrast, "Russia should not allow gay couples to raise children" is a
normative statement since it is not a claim about what is true, but what ought to be true, relative to some standard of evaluation (for example, a moral or legal
standard). An important idea within philosophy, which is often traced back to
the Scottish philosopher David Hume (1711-1776), is that statements about what
ought to be the case (i.e., normative statements) can never be derived from
statements about what is the case (i.e., descriptive statements). This is known
within philosophy as the is-ought gap. The problem with the above argument
is that it attempts to infer a normative statement from a purely descriptive
statement, violating the is-ought gap. We can see the problem by constructing
a counterexample. Suppose that in society x it is true that children raised by gay
couples have psychological problems. However, suppose that in that society
people do not accept that the state should do what it can to decrease harm to
children. In this case, the conclusion, that the state should discourage gay
couples from raising children, does not follow. Thus, we can see that the
argument depends on a missing or assumed premise that is not explicitly stated.
That missing premise must be a normative statement, in order that we can infer
the conclusion, which is also a normative statement. There is an important
general lesson here: Many times an argument with a normative conclusion will
depend on a normative premise which is not explicitly stated. The missing
normative premise of this particular argument seems to be something like this:
The state should always do what it can to decrease harm to children.
Notice that this is a normative statement, which is indicated by the use of the
word "should". There are many other words that can be used to capture
normative statements such as: good, bad, and ought. Thus, we can reconstruct
the argument, filling in the missing normative premise like this:
- Children who are raised by gay couples often have psychological and
emotional problems.
- The state should always do what it can to decrease harm to children.
- Therefore, the state should discourage gay couples from raising
children. (from 1-2)
However, although the argument is now in better shape, it is still invalid because
it is still possible for the premises to be true and yet the conclusion false. In
order to show this, we just have to imagine a scenario in which both the
premises are true and yet the conclusion is false. Here is one counterexample to
the argument (there are many). Suppose that while it is true that children of gay
couples often have psychological and emotional problems, the rate of psychological problems in children raised by gay couples is actually lower than
in children raised by heterosexual couples. In this case, even if it were true that
the state should always do what it can to decrease harm to children, it does not
follow that the state should discourage gay couples from raising children. In
fact, in the scenario I've described, just the opposite would seem to follow: the
state should discourage heterosexual couples from raising children.
But even if we suppose that the rate of psychological problems in children of
gay couples is higher than in children of heterosexual couples, the conclusion
still doesn't seem to follow. For example, it could be that the reason that
children of gay couples have higher rates of psychological problems is that in a
society that is not yet accepting of gay couples, children of gay couples will face
more teasing, bullying and general lack of acceptance than children of
heterosexual couples. If this were true, then the harm to these children isn't so
much due to the fact that their parents are gay as it is to the fact that their
community does not accept them. In that case, the state should not necessarily
discourage gay couples from raising children. Here is an analogy: At one point
in our country's history (if not still today) it is plausible that the children of black
Americans suffered more psychologically and emotionally than the children of
white Americans. But for the government to discourage black Americans from
raising children would have been unjust, since it is likely that if there was a
higher incidence of psychological and emotional problems in black Americans,
then it was due to unjust and unequal conditions, not to the black parents, per
se. So, to return to our example, the state should only discourage gay couples
from raising children if they know that the higher incidence of psychological
problems in children of gay couples isn't the result of any kind of injustice, but is
due to the simple fact that the parents are gay.
Thus, one way of making the argument (at least closer to) valid would be to add
the following two missing premises:
- The rate of psychological problems in children of gay couples is
higher than in children of heterosexual couples.
- The higher incidence of psychological problems in children of gay
couples is not due to any kind of injustice in society, but to the fact
that the parents are gay.
- Children who are raised by gay couples often have psychological and
emotional problems.
- The rate of psychological problems in children of gay couples is
higher than in children of heterosexual couples.
- The higher incidence of psychological problems in children of gay
couples is not due to any kind of injustice in society, but to the fact
that the parents are gay.
- The state should always do what it can to decrease harm to children.
- Therefore, the state should discourage gay couples from raising
children. (from 1-4)
In this argument, premises 2-4 are the missing or assumed premises. Their
addition makes the argument much stronger, but making them explicit enables
us to clearly see what assumptions the argument relies on in order for the
argument to be valid. This is useful since we can now clearly see which premises
of the argument we may challenge as false. Arguably, premise 4 is false, since
the state shouldn't always do what it can to decrease harm to children. Rather,
it should only do so as long as such an action didn't violate other rights that the
state has to protect or create larger harms elsewhere.
The important lesson from this example is that supplying the missing premises of an argument is not always a simple matter. In the example above, I have used the principle of charity to supply missing premises. Mastering this skill is truly an art (rather than a science) since there is never just one correct way of doing it (cf. section 1.5) and because it requires a lot of skilled practice.
Assuring, guarding and discounting
As we have seen, arguments often have complex structures including subarguments (recall that a subargument is an argument for one of the premises of the main argument). But in practice people do not always give further reasons or argument in support of every statement they make. Sometimes they use certain rhetorical devices to cut the argument short, or to hint at a further argument without actually stating it. There are three common strategies for doing this:
Assuring: informing someone that there are further reasons although one
is not giving them now
Guarding: weakening one's claims so that it is harder to show that the
claims are false
Discounting: anticipating objections that might be raised to one's claim or argument as a way of dismissing those objections.
We will discuss these in order, starting with assuring. Why would we want to
assure our audience? Presumably when we make a claim that isn't obvious and
that the audience may not be inclined to believe. For example, if I am trying to
convince you that the United States is one of the leading producers of CO2
emissions, then I might cite certain authorities such as the Intergovernmental
Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) as saying so. This is one way of assuring our
audience: by citing authorities. There are many ways to cite authorities, some
examples of which are these:
Dentists agree that...
Recent studies have shown...
It has been established that...
Another way of assuring is to comment on the strength of one's own
convictions. The rhetorical effect is that by commenting on how sure you are
that something is true, you imply, without saying, that there must be very strong
reasons for what you believe - assuming that the audience believes you are a
reasonable person, of course. Here are some ways of commenting on the
strength of one's beliefs:
I'm certain that...
I'm sure that...
I can assure you that...
Over the years, I have become convinced that...
I would bet a million dollars that...
Yet another way of assuring one's audience is to make an audience member feel
that it would be stupid, odd, or strange to deny the claim one is making. One
common way to do this is by implying that every sensible person would agree
with the claim. Here are some examples:
Everyone with any sense agrees that...
Of course, no one will deny that...
There is no question that...
No one with any sense would deny that...
Another common way of doing this is by implying that no sensible person would
agree with a claim that we are trying to establish as false:
It is no longer held that...
No intelligent person would ever maintain that...
You would have to live under a rock to think that...
Assurances are not necessarily illegitimate, since the person may be right and
may in fact have good arguments to back up the claims, but the assurances are
not themselves arguments and a critical thinker will always regard them as
somewhat suspect. This is especially so when the claim isn't obviously true.
Next, we will turn to guarding. Guarding involves weakening a claim so that it is
easier to make that claim true. Here is a simple contrast that will make the
point. Consider the following claims:
- All U.S. Presidents were monogamous
- Almost all U.S. Presidents were monogamous
- Most U.S. Presidents were monogamous
- Many U.S. Presidents were monogamous
- Some U.S. Presidents were monogamous
The weakest of these claims is E, whereas the strongest is A and each claims
descending from A-E is increasingly weaker. It doesn't take very much for E to
be true: there just has to be at least one U.S. President who was monogamous.
In contrast, A is much less likely than E to be true because it require every U.S.
President to have been monogamous. One way of thinking about this is that
any time A is true, it is also true that B-E is true, but B-E could be true without A
being true. That is what it means for a claim to be stronger or weaker. A weak
claim is more likely to be true whereas a strong claim is less likely to be true. E
is much more likely to be true than A. Likewise, D is somewhat more likely to be
true than C, and so on.
So, guarding involves taking a stronger claim and making it weaker so there is
less room to object to the claim. We can also guard a claim by introducing a
probability clause such as, "it is possible that..". and "it is arguable that..". or
by reducing our level of commitment to the claim, such as moving from "I know
that x" to "I believe that x". One common use of guarding is in reconstructing
arguments with missing premises using the principle of charity (section 1.9). For
example, if an argument is that "Tom works for Merrill Lynch, so Tom has a
college degree," the most charitable reconstruction of this argument would fill
in the missing premise with "most people who work for Merrill Lynch have
college degrees" rather than "everyone who works for Merrill Lynch has a
college degree". Here we have created a more charitable (plausible) premise
by weakening the claim from "all" to "most," which as we have seen is a kind of
guarding.
Finally, we will consider discounting. Discounting involves acknowledging an
objection to the claim or argument that one is making, while dismissing that
same objection. The rhetorical force of discounting is to make it seem as
though the argument has taken account of the objections - especially the ones
that might be salient in a person's mind. The simplest and most common way of
discounting is by using the "A but B" locution. Contrast the following two
claims:
- The worker was inefficient, but honest.
- The worker was honest, but inefficient.
Although each statement asserts the same facts, A seems to be recommending the worker, whereas B doesn't. We can imagine A continuing: "And so the manager decided to keep her on the team". We can imagine B continuing: "Which is why the manager decided to let her go". This is what we can call the "A but B" locution. The "A but B" locution is a form of discounting that introduces what will be dismissed or overridden first and then follows it by what is supposed to be the more important consideration. By introducing the claim to be dismissed, we are discounting that claim. There are many other words that can be used as discounting words instead of using "but". Table 2 below gives a partial list of words and phrases that commonly function as discounting terms.
although | even if | but | nevertheless |
---|---|---|---|
though | while | however | nonetheless |
even though | whereas | yet | still |
Exercise
Supply the missing premise or premises needed in order to
make the following arguments valid. Try to make the premises as
plausible as possible while making the argument valid (which is to apply
the principle of charity).
- Ed rides horses. Therefore, Ed is a cowboy.
- Tom was driving over the speed limit. Therefore, Tom was doing
something wrong.
- If it is raining then the ground is wet. Therefore, the ground must be
wet.
- All elves drink Guinness, which is why Olaf drinks Guinness.
- Mark didn't invite me to homecoming. Instead, he invited his friend
Alexia. So he must like Alexia more than me.
- The watch must be broken because every time I have looked at it, the
hands have been in the same place.
- Olaf drank too much Guinness and fell out of his second story
apartment window. Therefore, drinking too much Guinness caused
Olaf to injure himself.
- Mark jumped into the air. Therefore, Mark landed back on the
ground.
- In 2009 in the United States, the net worth of the median white
household was $113,149 a year, whereas the net worth of the median
black household was $5,677. Therefore, as of 2009, the United States
was still a racist nation.
- The temperature of the water is 212 degrees Fahrenheit. Therefore, the water is boiling.
- Capital punishment sometimes takes innocent lives, such as the lives
of individuals who were later found to be not guilty. Therefore, we
should not allow capital punishment.
- Allowing immigrants to migrate to the U.S. will take working class jobs
away from working class folks. Therefore, we should not allow
immigrants to migrate to the U.S.
- Prostitution is a fair economic exchange between two consenting
adults. Therefore, prostitution should be allowed.
- Colleges are more interested in making money off of their football
athletes than in educating them. Therefore, college football ought to
be banned.
- Edward received an F in college Algebra. Therefore, Edward should
have studied more.
Answers
- 1. Anyone who rides horses is a cowboy.
- Driving over the speed limit is wrong.
- It is raining.
- Olaf is an elf.
- Any time a person has a choice of who to take to homecoming, they will
take the person they like the most.
- I have looked at the watch in frequent intervals - much more often than every 12 hours.
- Only those who have drank too much fall out of apartment windows.
- Mark is on Earth and is unassisted by any devices that help him overcome the Earth's gravity.
- Any nation in which there is a large discrepancy between net worths of
different races is a racist nation.
- The water is at sea level.
- First missing premise: We should not allows policies that have the
potential of taking innocent lives, unless there is a very good reason to do so. Second missing premise: there is no very good reason to allow
capital punishment.
- First missing premise: We should not allow policies that take working
class jobs away from working class folks, unless there is some very good
reason to do so. Second missing premise: there is no very good reason
to allow immigration that would offset the harm done to working class
folks.
- Any fair economic exchange between consenting adults should be
allowed.
- Anything that privileges using a student-athlete to make money for the
college over that student-athlete's education should be banned.
- Any student who receives an F in a course should have studied more for
that course.
Exercise
Which rhetorical techniques (assuring, guarding, discounting)
are being using in the following passages?
- Although drilling for oil in Alaska will disrupt some wildlife, it is better
than having to depend on foreign oil, which has the tendency to draw
us into foreign conflicts that we would otherwise not be involved in.
- Let there be no doubt: the entity that carried out this attack is a known
terrorist organization, whose attacks have a characteristic style - a style
that is seen in this attack today.
- Privatizing the water utilities in Detroit was an unprecedented move
that has garnered a lot of criticism. Nonetheless, it is helping Detroit
to recover from bankruptcy.
- Most pediatricians agree that the single most important factor in
childhood obesity is eating sugary, processed foods, which have
become all too common in our day and age.
- Although not every case of AIDS is caused by HIV, it is arguable that most are.
- Abraham Lincoln was probably our greatest president since he helped
keep together a nation on the brink of splintering into two.
- No one with any sense would support Obamacare.
- Even if universal healthcare is expensive, it is still the just thing to do.
- While our country has made significant strides in overcoming explicit
racist policies, the wide disparity of wealth, prestige and influence that
characterize white and black Americans shows that we are still
implicitly a racist country.
- Recent studies have show that there is no direct link between vaccines
and autism.
Answers
- Discounting
- Assuring
- Discounting
- Assuring
- Discounting
- Guarding
- Assuring
- Discounting
- Discounting
- Assuring