• Unit 2: Søren Kierkegaard

    Søren Aabye Kierkegaard (1813–1855) was a Danish Christian philosopher, theologian, and social critic, widely considered a founding existentialist figure. Convinced that the Christian faith had gone astray, Kierkegaard was a fierce critic of religious dogma. In Kierkegaard's view, you must earn your relationship with God through dedication and suffering.

    According to Kierkegaard, a person becomes a committed, responsible human being by making difficult decisions and sacrifices. The force of Kierkegaard's philosophy rests in the notion that human life is paradoxical and absurd and that confronting this absurdity makes us fully human (a theme revisited by Albert Camus, as we will discuss in Unit 8).

    This unit introduces you to Kierkegaard's life and religious philosophy, along with an overview of themes that later philosophers such as Jean-Paul Sartre and Simone de Beauvoir will call "existentialism". These key existentialist themes include the notions of commitment and responsibility, absurdity, anxiety, and authenticity.

    This unit will also note the work of Blaise Pascal (1623–1662) as a fellow theistic existentialist to Kierkegaard. Many philosophers believe Pascal was a precursor to the existentialist movement due to his concerns about the constraints of human existence or "finitude", perpetual change, uncertainty, suffering in human life, and the irrationality of human behavior.

    Completing this unit should take you approximately 4 hours.

    • 2.1: Kierkegaard's Philosophical Thinking

      Many consider Søren Kierkegaard (1813–1855), the Danish philosopher, theologian, critic, and poet, the first modern existentialist. He was deeply concerned with what philosophers call the "human condition". So long as we live, we are imprisoned in a world of striving, aspiration, and suffering. The human predicament is inextricably linked to our quest for absolutes and the frustrating knowledge that absolutes are out of reach. Kierkegaard wanted to help humans find meaning in their existence as mortal, finite, and time-bound beings.

    • 2.2: Kierkegaard's Religious Existentialism in Relation to Pascal

      Kierkegaard lived most of his life in Denmark, where his extremely devout father cast a terrible shadow over his childhood. Kierkegaard's father had cursed God in desperation for the poverty that enveloped his son's upbringing. Kierkegaard's father also sinned by having an extramarital affair with his future bride, Kierkegaard's mother. Kierkegaard (the son, our philosopher) was also troubled by physical problems and was rarely permitted to go outside owing to physical health issues (Kierkegaard and the Crisis in Religion Part 1, 24:28).

      Kierkegaard was tortured by the original sin he believed he inherited from his father. He went so far as to call off his engagement to his beloved fiancée Regina Olsen because he felt unworthy of her. He began behaving badly in public to get her to leave him since he lacked the strength to end the relationship. In addition to an incident that involved a local paper he despised and his polemics against the Lutheran church, Kierkegaard was deeply affected by these conflicts and a pervasive melancholy he inherited from his father. Kierkegaard also strongly believed the church had betrayed the true meaning of Christianity (Kierkegaard and the Crisis in Religion Part 1, 30:35).

    • 2.3: Kierkegaard's Analysis of Faith in Fear and Trembling

      In his book Fear and Trembling (1843), Kierkegaard focuses on the impossibility of understanding Abraham's willingness to sacrifice his son, Isaac. We cannot appeal to an objective feature in our lives to determine whether Abraham, "the Father of Faith", is a murderer or God's servant:

      Since public reason cannot decide the issue for us, we must decide for ourselves as a matter of religious faith.

      Kierkegaard did not justify Abraham's behavior in moral or ethical terms:

      The ethical expression for what Abraham did is that he would murder Isaac; the religious expression is that he would sacrifice Isaac; but precisely in this contradiction consists the dread which can well make a man sleepless, and yet Abraham is not what he is without this dread.

      – Fear and Trembling, Chapter 2

      The justification is purely religious or existential. The contrasting categories are the universal (social morality) and the particular (the individual who must make choices). The universal cannot be in a direct, personal relationship with God; only the individual can.

      The existing individual is the position Abraham occupies by his choice to sacrifice Isaac:

      Faith is precisely this paradox, that the individual as the particular is higher than the universal is justified over against it, is not subordinate but superior – yet in such a way, be it observed, that it is the particular individual who, after he has been subordinated as the particular to the universal, now through the universal becomes the individual who as the particular is superior to the universal, for the fact that the individual as the particular stands in an absolute relation to the absolute.

      – Fear and Trembling, Chapter 3

      According to Kierkegaard, Abraham is a "Knight of Faith" rather than a "Knight of Infinite Resignation" or a tragic hero: he not only obeyed God's commands, but he retained the hope that Isaac would be returned to him during this life. The "Knight of Infinite Resignation" would not have this hope. The tragic hero makes sacrifices in the service of societal norms.

      Abraham's sacrifice represents a teleological suspension of the ethical rather than an outright abandonment. His duty to sacrifice Isaac was a duty. However, it is not one that can manifest itself in societal ethics:

      Abraham recognizes a duty to something higher than both his social duty not to kill an innocent person and his personal commitment to his beloved son, viz. his duty to obey God's commands. However, he cannot give an intelligible ethical justification of his act to the community in terms of social norms, but must simply obey the divine command.

      Kirkegaard's concept of the "leap of faith" was a movement against reason itself, a movement that also placed Abraham outside of the ethical.

    • 2.4: Kierkegaard's Notion of Despair in The Sickness unto Death

      Despair is the "sickness unto death" (the title of Kirkegaard's 1849 book) and "is inherent to the human condition". Despair results from an "imbalance" or condition within the self and is resolved only through a relationship with God.

      Kirkegaard describes three forms of despair:

      1. being unaware of being in despair;
      2. being aware of being in despair but believing you cannot do anything about it; and
      3. defiantly rejecting the concept itself.


      The process of working through despair traverses from ignorance to defiance. This process involves the development of the self as an existing individual in a relationship with God.

      One way to think about the development of the self is in terms of our various relationships. The self is not simply a combination of mind (or soul) and body but a process of relationships. The individual must consider how their beliefs and attitudes relate to, match up with, and comport with how one is or how we exist in the world.

      Developing the self is a continual process of synthesizing and relating various features of the self to everything else. This process of realizing the self is dynamic, implying continuous activity, effort, and renewal. Contrast this process with viewing the self and religious belief as static: a set of habits we form and fix.

      Kierkegaard proposes three levels or stages of individual existence that humans must pass through to become an authentic self. Those who live at the first level, the aesthetic, might expect to encounter meaninglessness and irresponsibility, entertainment, and pleasure. These people are motivated by satisfaction rather than meaningful commitments to something larger than themselves, which leads to a life of despair. According to Kierkegaard, this mode of living is the norm rather than the exception for most people.

      Kierkegaard proposed that our lives are distinctively unique because the sum of our experiences differs from everyone else's. Our most extreme and intense experiences – those that cause fear and trembling, sickness to the point of death, and dread – are of the utmost importance. Experiencing these powerful experiences forces us to leave the safety of our aesthetic way of life.

      The second level of existence is the ethical. We must embark on a journey of self-discovery by making choices that commit us to a particular direction in life. This enables humans to demonstrate consistency, coherency, and responsibility (which they lacked in the aesthetic) while reinforcing societal values that transcend individual desires.

      The third level is the religious sphere, which is inextricably linked. The ethical and religious spheres are based on recognizing a higher reality that gives significance to actions. Living in the ethical realm requires a commitment to some universal ethical rules; living in the religious sphere entails an immediate and direct relationship with the Eternal. This is the highest plane of existence for Kierkegaard, yet he believes that almost no one lives a truly religious life.

      The ethical life is characterized by duty, while the religious life is characterized by the "passionate inwardness" of subjectivity in direct relation to God and the Absolute. The ethical is preserved in the religious. To be subjective is to look inward, to seek a truthful relationship with God. Subjectivity is a type of passion that is "subjectivity's highest expression". In this passion, truth becomes a paradox. Subjectivity's passionate inwardness comprehends the paradox of the eternal existing in time.

    • Unit 2 Assessment

      • Receive a grade