This article gives an overview of Heidegger's concept of "sense". Do you agree that it's not obvious that the question of "being" should be asked in terms of the word "sense"? How might assuming that the many senses of being can actually be organized around one focal sense limit our existential understanding of being?
The Concept of "Sense" in the Seinsfrage
Sense, Horizon, and Time
I
claimed that Heidegger does not successfully (i.e., phenomenologically)
demonstrate that the Seinsfrage must be formulated in terms of the
focal sense of being, as contrasted with the many senses of being. There
is, however, a further supposition Heidegger makes in his formulation
of the Seinsfrage that cannot be passed over here: viz., that the sense
of being, whatever it might be, can only be determined by reference to
the "horizon" in terms of which beings are understood. The concept of
the "horizon" is transcendental, and denotes an a priori condition of
possibility (not in the Kantian, formal sense, but rather in the
phenomenological, concrete sense of a condition that can itself be
exhibited in phenomenological intuition and, therefore, evidence). An
horizon gives light to whatever appears within its limits (peras), and
here, what appears within its limits are beings. The thesis that the
sense of being can only be determined by reference to an horizon is
logically independent of the thesis that the horizon is time, however
closely related these two theses are to one another in the conceptual
economy of Being and Time (so closely related that we hardly ever
distinguish between them). That the sense of being must be determined in
terms of a horizon only means that, whatever the sense of being might
be, it can only appear in the light cast by a transcendental condition.
To assert that time is the horizon in which any understanding of being
moves is to assert that it occupies the office of such a condition, and
as such enjoys priority over being as the foundation of its sense (and,
therefore, as what enables us to fix its sense). Thus, before Heidegger
has even attempted to offer an interpretation of time, he has already
assigned it a definite place in ontological inquiry: viz., that of a
condition. Furthermore, because of the equivalence between (1) time as
the horizon of the sense of being and (2) time as the horizon of
Dasein's understanding of being, the next steps of the inquiry have been
clearly delineated: it must be shown that time conditions Dasein's
understanding of being. An existential analytic therefore becomes
necessary. The concept of horizon interposes time between being and
beings, such that beings understandingly appear to Dasein only insofar
as they are temporally projected by Dasein via what Heidegger terms its
"potentiality-for-being" (Seinkönnen; pouvoir-être). If (1) the
Seinsfrage is formulated in terms of the focal, unified sense of being,
which commands the totality of its many senses, and if, moreover, (2)
this sense of being can only be disclosed, not via a definition of any
sort, but rather as an horizon, and if, finally, (3) the horizon is
itself defined as time, then it is only by way of Dasein's deployment of
temporality in thrown projection that the sense of being can be
disclosed. In this way of posing the Seinsfrage, time enjoys
transcendental priority over being, so much so that fundamental ontology
becomes reducible to "temporal science," where time is interpreted in
an explicitly transcendental manner, due to the form of the Seinsfrage
and, more specifically, the dependence of the sense of being on its
horizon.
But Dasein is an entity whose sense is itself
dependent on the prior givenness of the sense of being. Claude Romano
has compellingly demonstrated that Heidegger's project in Being and Time
and Basic Problems of Phenomenology fails because his analysis of
Dasein's temporality ultimately yields only three senses of being, none
of which can be identified with the sense of being in general. These
three senses are Zuhandenheit, Vorhandenheit, and Existenz. The first
two depend on the ecstasis of the present and its modification in the
now (Gegenwart, Jetzt), and the third depends on the ecstasis of the
authentic future (Zukunft). The problem is that these three ecstases,
together with their corresponding schemata, do not in any way seem to
converge in or disclose a focal sense, but are rather irreducibly
diverse, so much so that they render the sense of being equivocal.
Heidegger's interpretation of time does not establish the focal sense of
being, but only mutually irreducible senses of being. To be sure, all
of these senses refer to or are based on time, but they are mutually
irreducible senses of different entities, and do not disclose a focal
sense that encompasses them all. I agree with Romano's interpretation,
which further confirms not only that Heidegger does not demonstrate in
the introduction to Being and Time that the sense of being is given in
and determines the understanding of being (and so can become an object
of ontological inquiry), but also that he has not demonstrated this by
the end of Being and Time and Basic Problems of Phenomenology, which
contains "a new elaboration of Division 3 of Part 1 of Being and Time,"
where Heidegger intended to finally disclose the sense of being in light
of the horizon of time. Heidegger's recognition of this failure led
him to realize that his formulation of the Seinsfrage stemmed, not from
die Sache selbst, but rather from the one aspect of the history of
ontology that survived the otherwise radical Destruktion he carries out
in Being and Time: the formulation of the Seinsfrage as a question about
the sense of being, to which all other senses can be referred and in
which they find their unitary ground. In the 1930s, Heidegger will
abandon the project of trying to account for the sense of being by way
of time. He will abandon the concept of "sense" in his formulation of
the Seinsfrage. In the Kehre, he will focus on the co-belonging of Being and Time in the Ereignis, without prioritizing one over the other,
according to a decidedly post-transcendental Fragestellung hinting in
the direction of a phenomenology of givenness.