This article gives an overview of Heidegger's concept of "sense". Do you agree that it's not obvious that the question of "being" should be asked in terms of the word "sense"? How might assuming that the many senses of being can actually be organized around one focal sense limit our existential understanding of being?
Is There a Body without Flesh?
The Myth of Experience
Is there a body
without flesh? The question seems as rhetorical as the inverse one
Falque poses to Henry. We already know Henry's answer: A body cannot
appear, and thus be, unless it is first given to flesh. This rule
applies whether I am dealing with a material body in the world or with
the corps propre, my own body. In the one case as in the other, a body
cannot appear unless it is first given to sensibility, and nothing is
given to the senses I call mine unless it affects me. Apart from this
affective instance, without a flesh that is impressional, I have no way
of saying whether I am dealing with the front of a thing or its
backside, its blue hue or hardness, girth or speed, or with its
disappearance, because I know nothing about it. I can offer no
description, phenomenological or otherwise. Of what would it be the
description? I have no access to a thing unless it is given to me in
experience, or in imagination, as composed of what is so given. Unless
I can be affected, unless I am endowed with flesh, nothing like a body
can appear and I am simply not entitled to speak of a body, not even as
an idea.
Why then ask whether there is a body without flesh
if such a possibility for these decisive reasons is unintelligible? Can
any further precision show the question to be worth the annoyance of
posing and the labor of investigating? What is a body and what is flesh?
According to the standard definition, a body in general is a material
thing bearing sensible or intelligible properties - the categories of
Aristotle (time, change, motion, quality, size, place, etc.), or the
sensible qualities of Galileo or Descartes (extension, figure, etc.),
the pure forms of intuition of Kant (space and time), or the properties
of sub-atomic physics (spin, location, charge, mass, etc.). Even in the
latter cases, where the properties of a body are not known through the
senses, but through instruments of measurement that have been designed
to detect and record what the senses cannot, senses nevertheless must
intervene to "read" such instruments. The physicist that denies that our
senses tell us the truth of the universe must consult the senses in
some way in order to arrive at that conclusion.
The
question can nevertheless be answered affirmatively. Yes, there is a
body without flesh. The universe is populated with bodies of this sort,
which are what they are independently of any appeal to flesh for their
appearance. First, for the strict reason that they do not appear to
flesh and do not affect it directly. In itself, flesh knows nothing
about them. Second, because they are what they are, and will be what
they will be, whatever we may wish to assert about flesh, or even if we
wish to ignore flesh, and what is given to it, altogether. It is not
even obvious that someone must observe the Large Hadron Collider, since
programs can be designed for that purpose, and register the events in
question with more subtlety and precision than the "naked eye". If we
were smart enough, we would program those computers also to interpret
the data better than we can, find errors in our assumptions, mistakes in
our models, and so on. From this perspective, not only is there a body
without flesh, perhaps an infinite number of them; in addition, if we
are to arrive at the truth of the bodies that populate the universe, we
must ignore flesh altogether.
Including our own? Nothing
prohibits the positive sciences from applying the same methods to the
human body they apply to the cosmos. Whether we are dealing with cell
biology, genetics, neuroscience, or the other cognitive sciences, no
reference to flesh is required, and it is not obvious how any discussion
of flesh, in Henry's sense, can be included in either the assumptions,
methods, or results of these fields. It is true that some forms of
cognitive research on so-called "live" subjects do involve prompting the
subject of research to "think about" or "imagine" an object, and so
forth. Through a process of trial and error, it is possible to correlate
material events in the brain with reported experiences, so that
eventually consciousness would be, as Daniel Dennett says,
"explained". What seems to be, and is called, an experience of
something, is in fact, caused or occasioned by material episodes of
which we are entirely unaware. Edit the episode (or what codes for it),
edit the experience. Even if some are uncomfortable with the idea of
dismissing human experience as entirely illusory, the scientific
position is clear: the material, bodily event is phenomenal; the
experience of sensing and of sensed, scientifically speaking at least,
is epiphenomenal, or worse, illusory.
If such a conclusion
seems difficult to accept, resolving it goes beyond the purview of
science. Let politicians, therapists, pharmaceutical companies, social
workers, school teachers, and prison guards deal with the consequences.
Science must tell us only what is true. We must dare, precisely not to
think anymore, but to experiment. It is no longer the philosopher who
dethrones the gods of the mythmakers, but the scientist; and in the
universe of science, only one god is worthy of the name. Evidence. But
the etymology of the word is no longer its meaning. If e-videre means to
come from seeing, here in question is not seeing, nor even what is
seen, at least if that must involve and depend upon sensibility. Rather,
a certain way of determining and "explaining" the material world,
including what we do see, that is the arche and telos of science, the
limits of its veritas and its realitas. Is the ambition of science
anything but to establish once and for all a correct explanatory account
of the universe in all its dimensions on the basis of an exact
understanding of the causal relationships that govern its constituent
parts?
In any case, we are up against a problem. We have in
phenomenology a reference to flesh and to the sensing body as a
necessary condition of experience and definition of reality, and the
exclusion of any such reference in the natural sciences, as a condition
of any experimentation and also as a definition of reality. How should
one respond intellectually or practically to this
apparently-unresolvable dilemma cutting the history of reason in two? On
the one hand, the world of our experience, with all its sensible
delight - our ambitions, aims, and hopes, fears and regrets, joys and
sorrows, love and hate - this world of meaning, of sense, of value. On
the other, the empirically-observable, material world of bodies visible
to us, or detectable in dimensions far beyond what we can see - this
material world, the better understanding of which continues to benefit
humanity in myriad ways.
An objection arises: Where is the
dilemma? If the visible universe is an element, and a marvelous element,
of the world of experience, as of creation, then no rational person
ought to resist the desire to understand the mechanisms by which it
operates. Can one really suppose it to be a world of inert bodies in
which no meaning, no sense, can be found? The apparent contradiction
between sense and nonsense - here, the world of meaning and the world of
senseless bodies - covers over another one that is more difficult. We
are up against two incompatible definitions of the real. If so-called
"first-person" experience cannot be reduced, and what is observed in the
third-person can never be raised to the level of experiencing itself,
for what kind of correlation can we hope?