This article gives an overview of Heidegger's concept of "sense". Do you agree that it's not obvious that the question of "being" should be asked in terms of the word "sense"? How might assuming that the many senses of being can actually be organized around one focal sense limit our existential understanding of being?
Is There a Body without Flesh?
Embodied Mind: Thinking Matter
The opposition
just posited - between the world of meaning, on the one hand, and the
world of senseless, inert bodies, on the other - is it artificial or
contrived? Far from being a contradiction needing resolution, are these
worlds not already, originally and always, conjoined, as Merleau-Ponty
has taught us? Flesh is a body that is part - a body-part - of this
great body that is the universe (we leave aside the question of whether
another, or an infinite number of others, is possible). Flesh, the
living, sensing body, is a constituent part of the universe, even if it
has raised itself - but why "raised"? - to the level of self-awareness.
Admitting the worldly nature of flesh does not require us to nullify or
diminish the realm of meaning, the so-called "space" of reasons.
"Meaning is not a mysterious gift from outside nature," John McDowell
reminds us; to think so would commit us to a "rampant platonism".
Cognition, and the mind as such, is "embodied". In its acts of knowing
it need neither be absorbed by nor separated from what it knows, but is
or at least can be "simply present and available".
In
significant continuity with Merleau-Ponty's work, a growing field of
research now seeks to demonstrate the thesis that the fleshly body is a
worldly body, and to do so while respecting the prerogatives of both
phenomenology and science. To take one notable example, Evan Thompson
in Mind in Life aims to integrate phenomenology and cognitive science in
an "enactive" approach that promises to describe and explain at once:
"Starting from a recognition of the transcendental and hence
ineliminable status of experience, the aim would be to search for
morphodynamical principles that can both integrate the orders of matter,
life, and mind, and account for the originality of each order". Once a
dynamic morphology of sufficient complexity is recognized - made
possible by new topologies, differential geometry, etc. - it is possible
to "map," and then to demonstrate, dynamic and isomorphic relations
that arise between physiological systems and perceptual forms.
The effort to achieve such a demonstration, Thompson thinks, would have
been embraced by Merleau-Ponty, had a morphology of sufficient richness
and complexity been available to him. From this perspective, the remove
at which classical phenomenology stands vis-à-vis science, emblematic
of Husserl's Krisis (to say nothing of Heidegger's position), is not a
matter of principle, but only a contingent, conceptual constraint,
bounded as it was by the limits of the sciences then-available. In any
case, if Husserl thinks it is the task of phenomenology to assign the
sciences their ultimate meaning, it cannot accomplish this task unless a
genuine connection arises between phenomenology and the sciences it
purports to ground. Otherwise, phenomenology amounts to little more than
a series of one-sided assertions and pronouncements about the world of
experience, which the world of science can safely ignore. But if the
results of the sciences can be altered by taking into account
phenomenological insight, as advocates of this approach have shown, then
the sciences cannot afford to ignore it.
How should we
account for this development phenomenologically? How is it possible that
a phenomenological analysis according to the strict phenomenological
reduction of what is given in intuition, far from providing the antidote
to materialism, naturalism, or reductionism, is now enriched by it, to
the point of morphing into a "naturalized phenomenology"? We should
not fail to notice that protagonists of the enactive approach refuse
"objectivism" quite explicitly, and insist on the irreducible,
transcendental character of "experience" as the condition for the
possibility of the appearance of any object. In addition, and this point
is perhaps more important, we are not dealing with a conflation of
methods or perspectives, since the engagement with science goes hand in
hand with and is predicated upon the insistence on the importance and
irreducibility of the phenomenological perspective. One might reasonably
consider such an approach to offer a kind of concrete synthesis of mind
and world, rather than the a priori one Kant sought.
If the
world of experience is irreducible to the world of science and yet
integrated with it, is that not what we ought to expect and indicative
of a certain correctness? Or, alternatively, in order to effect such an
integration of phenomenology and science, has the concept of experience,
necessarily, become a concept of scientific experience alone? Or, yet
again, are we dealing with a Malebranchean parallelism that is simply
harder to detect because the lines now overlap, or intertwine, to use
Merleau-Ponty's word? What is involved in the reduction of experience to
scientific experience (that is, the experience of the scientist) and
what are its consequences? I will offer three objections, which will
lead us into a more refined and direct engagement with the question of
flesh and its relation to the body before opening onto a theological
question.
First, properly speaking, I do not and cannot have
an experience of my neurons as objects. It is true that I can connect my
own scull, let us call it le crâne propre, to a brain scanner, and vary
my thinking as I watch correlating parts of my brain light up on a
screen. On the basis of such correlations between my thought and my
body, can I ever claim to have an (original) experience of my neurons as
sensible or intellectual objects? It would be a reflective experience,
and nothing would keep me from learning something perceptually about my
body in this way. But what I observe on the screen is not my body and
can never be, at least if by body we mean the original, subjective body
in its original givenness to itself, its auto-affection, or
pre-reflective awareness.
Second, if what I observe is not my
body, but only a visual representation, can we say that the correlation
has proved successful, that we have evidence for it? Even if one
embraces the brilliant level of engagement of phenomenology with
science, even if one were to achieve the perfect accord of carnal
affectivity with the perception of the body, the problem of principle
remains: these are two irreducible orders of givenness, of
phenomenality. A fundamental practical problem also remains: Imagine a
real-time projection of every dynamic alteration of the organic body
flashed on a optic lens, available to the concrete perception of my eye -
visible. Is it even possible to perceive, organically, the immense
complex that is the organic body, all in one view?
A third
and parallel objection can also be raised. The possibility of such a
perception is highly-specific, and more often than not, prohibitively
expensive. What is given in it goes well beyond what is given in the
range of perceptual experience available to anyone. If the notion of
what is phenomenal - and, even more, its phenomenality - however
broadened and enriched, is available only to one who has already entered
into the scientific perspective, and if such a perspective excludes in
principle the subject that perceives, feels, or enjoys, then such an
approach can indeed admit perception, feeling, or enjoyment, but only on
the condition that they become what they are not, which is to say,
reports of a perception, feeling, or enjoyment. The problem is not that
such reports can be mistaken, which in any case might prove relevant for
the experiment, but rather that, in the phenomenality of such a report,
the original phenomenon is torn from its original givenness, apart from
the world, in order to disclose it in a visibility that is foreign to
it. Yes, the scientist engrossed practically in an experiment, or
theoretically in the effort to design or modify a model for what is
observed experimentally, also perceives - that is, sees through forms,
however rarified they may be. But experience has here been reduced to
scientific experience. It can be extended to the universal - taken as
universal experience - only by a decision.
If many suspect
the world of science and with it virtual reality, automation, and
so-called artificial intelligence have encroached too far, it is because
the lifeworld as living has been colonized by technology. That is why
those who adopt it, who prefer to experience the world or themselves as
mediated by technology, risk losing knowledge of the world or
themselves apart from it. "The information age will be the age of
idiots," claims Henry in 1987. The orgasm-feigning robot that will
cater to your every wish, or discipline you as programmed, perhaps when
you least expect it - or can it learn that you expect that? - is indeed a
body without flesh. "Life is but a motion of the limbs… why may we not
say , that all Automata… have an artificiall life?"