This article gives an overview of Heidegger's concept of "sense". Do you agree that it's not obvious that the question of "being" should be asked in terms of the word "sense"? How might assuming that the many senses of being can actually be organized around one focal sense limit our existential understanding of being?
Is There a Body without Flesh?
Eyes of Faith: Flesh of the Theological
These questions as far as they go remain phenomenological and do not
depend upon articles of faith. Nevertheless, Falque correctly detects in
Henry's Incarnation a liaison between Part II and Part III, between the
phenomenology of flesh stricto sensu, and Incarnation in "the Christian
sense". Here, Falque advances a second principle objection and a
positive claim: "[N]othing ensures, at least in reading Michel Henry's
work, that the divine incarnation in a flesh pure and simple
[Inkarnation] also expresses the becoming human of God [Menschwerdung]…
Only a theology of the body or of the purely organic, rather than a
unilateral phenomenology of the flesh, will be able to produce the
identification, frequently avoided by Michel Henry, between the carnal
incarnation of God and his historical and corporeal humanization in the
figure of the incarnate Word".
Falque seems to suspect that
Henry subsumes "Incarnation in the Christian Sense" under a general and
also inadequate phenomenology of incarnation. Far from providing an
account of incarnation in the Christian sense, Henry's phenomenology of
life glosses over it and renders it equivalent to the fleshly condition
of anyone. At best, Revelation becomes a mere moment of phenomenology,
rather than the absolute Transcendent. What is worse, it can hardly be
called "incarnate" or even "human," since it is fundamentally
dis-incorporated. Flesh without body, in this precise sense, is finally a
gnostic flesh, as a-corporal as a-cosmic. It is neither Christian nor
human. "A monadism and a modalism of the Henryan flesh would thus become
all the more dis-incorporated as the body would be destroyed and
absorbed into it".
In response to this precise objection,
let us consider more closely a text that Falque cites in support of
these claims and that seems to invite the charge of Spinozism. Henry
describes the living person [vivant] as "no more than a mode of it
[auto-impressionality]. In other words, it is something that has no
consistency by itself, but only as a manifestation, modification, or
peripeteia of a reality that is other than it". Read one way (as
Falque reads it), this passage seems to deny the integrity of creation,
and to assert a strange, if not to say false, relation with an a-cosmic,
unworldly, dis-incorporated reality. One cannot even say it is a
relation of dependence, which would already imply a consistency of its
own, but rather a relation that merely, as Spinoza might say, expresses
the absolute. If Henry means what Falque thinks he means here, Falque
would be right to reject it. But I think Henry is saying something else
entirely, and a better understanding of it will also shed light on
Falque's other objections.
I read Henry's phrase, "has no
consistency by itself," with Augustine rather than Spinoza in mind. If
Henry means that apart from Life and, in a deeper sense, apart from
God's own life given in Christ, human living dis-integrates, and lacks
unity or consistency, then Henry's claim is impeccably
phenomenologically and theologically precise. Neither here nor elsewhere
does Henry turn finite flesh into a dis-incorporate epiphenomenon
lacking all reality. Nor does he claim it is only a "mode" of absolute
life in the manner of Spinoza. Henry is claiming, instead, at least
three things: 1) Finite flesh is not autonomous absolutely. The pretense
to be itself on its own, by its own power, is illusory. It cannot
give itself its own law if it cannot give itself its own life. 2) Flesh
can be a site in which life manifests itself, or alternatively can be a
site where life is denatured. Whether one or the other eventuality
ensues is, in part, a function of the kind of relation flesh maintains
with the life that gives it to itself. 3) Infinite Life, strictly
speaking - insofar as it brings itself about in itself [se porte
soi-même en soi] - is, with respect to finite life, an alterity, "a
reality that is other than it".
Here we have a fundamental
distinction between finite and infinite flesh, an alterity not reducible
to the alterity of the finite other. It expresses in phenomenological
terms what the creature-creator distinction expresses theologically. As
fundamental as it is, however, that distinction does not destroy the
fundamental relation that is creation. But Falque does not see this
distinction in Henry, or does not find it strong enough: "There is a
distance in the relation of the human to God… that is not identical to
the distance of sin". For Henry, once again, finite life cannot "bring
itself about in itself". The power to give life, even life to itself - a
power at infinite remove from any human power - it forever lacks. I am
not "my own" life and will never be. Is this not, in fact, the orthodox
concept of creation? God is Life and the giver of life, and all the
living bear a relation to God by virtue of their living condition.
It is not simply creation that Falque finds missing, but also an
orthodox concept of incarnation. Somewhat surprisingly, he suspects that
Henry denies that the Son of God has taken on the human condition in
every way but sin. Where Henry writes that the "one who took on flesh in
Christ was not an ordinary man but the Word of God" (160 / 69, Falque's
emphasis, citing Incarnation, 231 / 331), Falque interprets Henry as
denying that Jesus was born in human likeness, just like any of us, with
a carnal body of visible matter. But here again nothing prohibits us
from reading this differently. The one who has taken on human likeness
in the man Jesus is not just anyone, is not you or me, but rather the
One who is in himself the Word. Of course Jesus is a man like any other,
but he is not only a man like any other, since he is in his person the
very Word of God. Falque wants to compliment an emphasis on the
"exemplary" with an emphasis on "the ordinary life and common fleshly
humanity of the Son of God".
In addition to an adequate
conception of the humanity of Jesus, it is also the uniqueness or
singularity of the incarnation that Falque wishes to safeguard. Now
citing "the philosopher" Merleau-Ponty: "the Incarnation changes
everything". And Falque is right. Incarnation in the Christian sense
does change everything. But Falque thinks incarnation in Henry's sense,
like the astral flesh of Marcion, or the angelic flesh of Jakob Böhme,
cannot "change" anything, strictly speaking. How could it if the
auto-impressional flesh it involves is forever a-temporal, invisible,
dis-incorporated, and thus entirely unlike the temporal, visible, bodily
appearance of the Word made flesh, which in the words of John, "we have
heard… we have seen with our eyes… we have looked at and touched with
our hands"? If we are to affirm these words, as we do, must we not
side with Falque against Henry on this point? The theology Falque wishes
to preserve is not in question here, but only the phenomenology, and
thus the conditions under which (the way) the revelation of God in
Christ comes to manifestation.
How does the affirmation that
the Word was made flesh in a flesh like ours go together
phenomenologically with the theological singularity of the Word made
flesh, indeed its primacy? For as we have seen, it is not just any
incarnation in question, in your flesh or mine, but the incarnation of
the One who is the Word. To be more precise, how must we describe,
following Nicholas of Cusa but this time phenomenologically, the
co-incidence of the following two apparently-irreconcilable opposites:
The man Jesus is both seen and heard, and rejected as God by many? Can
a phenomenology that starts with visible body tout court do it? We
should avoid any hasty appeal to faith to explain the difference between
acceptance and rejection. Falque's intuitions are correct: it is not
only the eyes of faith that see God in Jesus, but the sensible eyes of
the body, and also the intellectual "eyes" of those who contemplate him.
But by insisting that the one who sees Jesus - i.e. sees him "bodily" -
does indeed perceive God in the flesh, has Falque left any room for
those who wish to deny it, as many did and still do? After all, they do
not reject what they see, a man in space and time, visible like any
other. Nor is it a different man, but the same one his followers also
see. What they reject is that this appearing man is God. (In this
precise respect Falque claims about the priority of the body are
correct. In the order of historical time, they see Jesus first, before
some come to believe he is the Christ). But can the humanity of
precisely the Word made flesh be recognized as such by appealing first
or exclusively to the visibility of it, where the meaning of "flesh" is
blended with, and finally phenomenal as, the visible body? How then
could we come to terms with the invisibility of the Father? In the
Johannine text, Jesus says: "No one can come to me unless drawn by the
Father who sent me… Everyone who has heard and learned from the Father
comes to me. Not that anyone has seen the Father except the one who is
from God; he has seen the Father".
By refusing the
phenomenological privilege of invisible, auto-impressional flesh, not
just the experience of flesh or life, but flesh as it undergoes
experiencing itself - is Falque committed to an exclusivism of the
sensed? Not necessarily. He does not refuse the fact of an invisible
dimension of flesh, but refuses it priority, and refuses to sever its
(visible) bond with the irreducibly visible, the "spread body". He
refuses the notion that flesh is invisible alone, sensing alone,
touching alone, in favor of a view that it is also, and at the same
time, visible, sensed, and touched - which is to say, is also body. Of
course, at one level, Falque's claims are entirely legitimate. This
"thing" I call my flesh "is" also this "thing" I call my body. The
distinctions Henry and others make between the subjective body, the
living body, the organic body, the objective body, and so on, these are
phenomenological declinations of the body as such. The body, as such,
"is" their unity. But only in flesh and as flesh is that unity
self-given. It is not given in its original phenomenality either in
perception or in sensibility.
If we wish to follow
Merleau-Ponty's path, as Falque does, either we must remain in an ontic
register that denies the fundamental, original, phenomenological
irreducibility of visible and invisible, world and life, and finally
flesh and Life, or we must enter into theological territory and with
eyes of faith recognize these twos as ones. One can offer a kind of
phenomenology from faith, as Emmanuel Falque does so well, but one can
also wonder whether, because this is a phenomenology of faith and from
the perspective of faith, it is theology more from "from above" than
"from below," despite everything. "Eyes of faith" here means, minimally,
hearing the Words of Christ and believing, and maximally, participating
fully in sacramental life. If we remain in the realm of sense
perception and confine our understanding of these realities to the sheer
ontic unities of flesh and body, body and world, flesh and world, we
seem committed to a theologically- and phenomenologically-questionable
materialism. If, instead, we understand seeing as seeing in the light of
faith, we must admit that it is faith that gives the incarnate unity in
question, Word and flesh, and Word made flesh. In the order of
perception, it is faith and not sensibility, or better faith with
sensibility, that gives the unity in question. The one who denies that
Jesus is Lord also sees Jesus, or could do so. In seeing Jesus they also
see the Lord, and deny him. But they do not deny what they see, Jesus.
Without the duplicity of appearing, one has either a kind of ontic
phenomenality, so to speak, or faith. But then he phenomenality of
faith, properly speaking, would seem to remain out of reach, since the
sensible has already, of itself, been so fully loaded with faith. It is a
way of thinking the unity of faith and phenomenological reason, but
perhaps one that risks compromising something of both. The theologian
must still bear the burden of describing phenomenologically what life
means, and what it means for that Word to give its life for the world,
for you and for me, what it means to live with it and in it and from it,
to "participate" in precisely that Life and no other, and to be made
able to do so. I am not confident all this can be done on the basis of
the phenomenality of the world alone. Of course, I understand "world"
here in Henry's sense and not that of Merleau-Ponty, and an objection to
the position I am sketching here might find in that fact a point of
dispute.
The charges of Gnosticism and Spinozism, in any
case, are misapplied and ultimately unhelpful, at least when it comes to
what clearly becomes the trajectory of Henry's final writings on
Christianity. Like Kierkegaard says life must be lived, Henry's writings
on Christianity must be read forward, but can only be understood
backward. Life does not save me from the world, nor do I need saving
from it. It simply gives itself otherwise and differently than what the
world gives and how the world gives. The givenness of the world (as much
as of the body and its bones) is and remains a givenness, but never a
self-givenness. This is a phenomenological claim, not a soteriological
one. The two should not be confused. But the decision to limit one's
understanding or definition of reality to the unilateral exteriority of
the world may indeed have soteriological implications. We may never come
to terms with what faith means, what faith is about - to say nothing of
creation, which is not a mere concept but also reality itself - if we
remain so limited.
* * *
A word remains to be said
about the engagement of phenomenology with science and its place in
these reflections. That area of study has its own merit, legitimacy, and
interest. The protagonists of such research deserve enormous praise,
with two small qualifications. First, the effort to correlate first- and
third-person perspectives risks slipping to a kind of scientism if only
those correlations ground the phenomenality and phenomenological
legitimacy of experiencing undergoing itself in flesh. The phenomena
arising in flesh are proper to flesh. The varying worldly vestiges of
it, including its practical action, illuminate only what a world can be
(including the world of science). They do not give or illuminate or
justify what is given in flesh in itself, which has its own
phenomenological integrity. Secondly, and for a related reason, science
will never prove God (and here we mean "science" and not "reason"). Nor
will it ever prove, for example, that Jesus is Lord. "If they do not
listen to Moses and the prophets, neither will they be convinced even if
someone rises from the dead". None of this can count in any way as a
failure of science, but only as a difference from phenomenology, and in
another way, a difference from faith.
Falque's phenomenology
of flesh and bone is clearly distinct from Henry's phenomenology of
life, and the distinctions between them merit further investigation. I
share the same theological commitments as Falque, and I hold in high
regard the profound spirit of his theological vision. These objections
are only about phenomenology, and in a secondary way about how
phenomenology relates to Christian faith, tactically speaking. I suspect
that ultimately Falque's objections to Henry presuppose that one has
already refused Henry's basic theses concerning phenomenality and the
duplicity of appearing. But new questions can also now be posed, this
time to Falque: Does the phenomenological priority of the body to the
flesh assume a theological acceptation of the body as sacramental, and
thus as theologically meaningful, as significant? If so, should we not
understand this to be a sacramental phenomenology? And if that is the
case, does it presuppose and depend upon the eyes of faith, or even
sacramental experience, for its phenomenality? In my view, the further
development of the phenomenology of life may also go in a sacramental
direction. Henry himself invites it, and it is not clear that a
rapprochement between their positions could not be found there.
In any case, one cannot avoid being struck by the subtle moments Falque
expresses thanks for the reprieve that arrives when Henry admits a kind
of "transcendent" life. But Falque does not put much stock in it. Why?
Because admitting it, he thinks, would make of Henry's work a total
contradiction and destroy its most important theses. But I think Falque
and with him almost all readers of Henry have missed something very
important. The phenomenology of life Henry finds in Christianity is not
reducible to his own. Henry discovers in Christianity a depth (of life)
that offers more than his own phenomenology on its own can provide, a
depth which later involves a reproach that overturns the entire
affective economy and the world of ethics it presupposes. If we must
turn to Words of Christ to see its contours and extent, nothing
prohibits us from reading Henry's final text, in part, as a response to
Falque's objections. If that is in any way the fruit of a combat
amoureux, for this we can also thank Emmanuel Falque.