Read these sections to learn and apply a visual method for determining the validity of categorical inferences: Venn diagrams. Note the four categorical forms and what they mean: universal affirmative, universal negative, particular affirmative, and particular negative. Get comfortable drawing Venn diagrams for categorical statements and shading in the area or drawing a star for the statements you are given.
Complete the exercises, checking your answers against the answer keys, translating the diagrams into statements, and using the Venn test of validity to determine the validity of the given categorical inferences.
Categorical logic
Consider the following argument:
- All humans are mortal
- All mortal things die
- Therefore, all humans die
If we were to apply the informal test of validity (from chapter 1) to this argument,
we would see that the argument is valid because it is not possible to imagine a
scenario in which the premises are true and yet the conclusion is false.
However, look at what happens if we try to translate it using propositional logic.
Since "all humans are mortal" is atomic, (i.e., it does not contain any truth
functional operators) we can translate it using the constant "H". The second
premise, "all mortal things die," is also atomic, so we can translate it using the
constant, "M". Finally, the conclusion, is yet another atomic statement, "All
humans die," which we can translate "D". But then the form of our argument is
just this:
- H
- M
- ∴ D
The problem is that this argument is not valid, which we can clearly see by constructing a truth table. Since there are three different atomic components, our truth table will be 8 rows. (In the following truth table, since the reference columns would just be identical to the premise and conclusion columns, I just collapsed the two in order to make the truth table less redundant)
H | M | D |
---|---|---|
T | T | T |
T | T | F |
T | F | T |
T | F | F |
F | T | T |
F | T | F |
F | F | T |
F | F | F |
Notice the second row of the truth table (which I have bolded). The premises
are both true on that row and yet the conclusion is false. That means that this
argument does not pass the truth table test of validity and so is invalid. But
clearly this argument is valid. If it is true that all humans are mortal and that all
mortal things die, then it must be true that all humans die. What this argument
reveals is one of the limitations of propositional logic. There are some
arguments that are intuitively valid (such as this one) but that cannot be shown
to be valid using the methods of propositional logic. This shows that we need
other kinds of formal logic to be able to capture a wider range of logically valid
inferences. Categorical logic allows us to supplement propositional logic with a
formal method that will handle arguments like this that propositional logic is
unable to handle.
Categorical logic is the logic that deals with the logical relationship between
categorical statements. A categorical statement is simply a statement about a
category or type of thing. For example, the first premise of the above argument
is a statement about the categories of humans and things that are mortal. The
second premise is a statement about the categories of things that are mortal
and things that die. Finally, the conclusion is a statement about humans and
things that die. Although you may think that this argument as a similar form as a
hypothetical syllogism, it is distinct from a hypothetical syllogism because the
premises are not composed of two different atomic propositions. Rather, each
premise contains only one atomic proposition.
In categorical logic, the logical terms (analogous to the truth functional
operators of propositional logic) are the terms "all" and "some". In contrast
with propositional logic, in categorical logic we will use capital letters to stand for categories of things in the world, rather than for atomic propositions. Thus,
we can represent the statement:
All humans are mortal
as
All H are M
where "H" stands for the category of "humans" and "M" stands for the
category, "things that are mortal". Notice that the categories are nouns or noun
phrases. Thus, instead of saying that the category is "mortal" I said the
category is "things that are mortal". It is important to recognize the difference
between how the capital letters are being used in categorical logic and how
they were used in propositional logic. In categorical logic, the capital letters
stand for noun phrases that denote categories of things in the world - for
example, "cars" or "things that are man-made" or "mammals" or "things that
are red".
In categorical logic, we will use what are called Venn diagrams to represent the logical relationships between the different kinds of categorical statements. A Venn diagram is simply a way of graphically representing the logical relationship between two different categorical statements. Below is a Venn diagram that represents the statement, "all humans are mortal".
Here is how to understand this Venn. There are two circles that represent the
two categories, "humans" and "things that are mortal". These two categories
are overlapping so that the intersection of those two categories (i.e. the place
where the two circles overlap) represents things that are both human and
mortal. Any shaded portions of the Venn diagram (by "shaded" I will mean
"blacked out") represent that there is nothing in that area of the category. So
the above Venn says that there is nothing in the category "humans" that is not
also in the category "things that are mortal". The above Venn also allows that
there are things that are in the category "things that are mortal" but that aren't
in the category "humans" (which is as it should be since, of course, dogs are
mortal and yet not human). So the reason the category "things that are mortal"
is left unshaded is that in saying "all humans are mortal" I leave open the
possibility that there are things that are not human and yet mortal.
As noted above, the statement, "all humans are mortal," has a particular form:
All H are M.
This is one of the four categorical forms. The way we will represent these
categorical forms generally are with an "S" (which stands for "subject term") and
a "P" (which stands for "predicate term"). Thus, the categorical statement, "all
humans are mortal," has the following categorical form:
All S are P
The way we interpret statements of this form are as follows: everything in the category S is also in the category P. This statement form is what we call a "universal affirmative," since it is a universal statement that does not contain a negation. There are three other categorical statement forms that you will have to become familiar with in order to do categorical logic. Here they are (with the name of the type of statement in parentheses to the right:
No S are P (universal negative)
Some S are P (particular affirmative)
Some S are not P (particular negative)
Here are three examples of statements that have these three forms
(respectively):
No reptiles give live birth
Some birds are taller than President Obama
Some birds don't fly
Notice that although these three statements don't have exactly the same form
as the statement forms above, they can be translated into those same forms. All
we have to do is figure out the noun phrase that describes each category that
the statement is referring to. Let's start with "no reptiles give live birth". This
categorical statement refers to two different categories: the category of
"reptiles" and the category of "things that give live birth". Notice, again, that I
added "things that..". to the predicate of the sentence ("give live birth")
because "give live birth" is not a description of a category. Rather, the way of
describing the category is with the noun phrase, "things that give live birth".
Using these two category descriptions, we can translate this sentence to have
the same form as its categorical form. All we have to do is substitute in the
name of the subject category (i.e., the "S" term) and the description of the
predicate category (i.e., the "P" term). Doing that will yield the following
sentence:
No reptiles are things that give live birth
Although this sentence sounds strange in English, it has the same form as the categorical form, no S are P, and this translation allows us to clearly see that it does and thus to see what the two categories are. Here is what the Venn diagram for this statement looks like:
This Venn diagram represents that there is nothing in the intersection of the two
categories, "reptiles" and "things that give live birth". If you think about it, this
is exactly what our original statement was saying: there isn't anything that is
both a reptile and gives live birth.
Let's look at the next statement, "some birds are taller than President Obama".
This is a statement not about all birds, but about some birds. What are the two
categories? One category is clearly "birds". The other category is "things that
are taller than President Obama". That may sound like a strange category, but it
is perfectly legitimate category. It includes things like adult ostriches, large
grizzly bears standing on their hind legs, giraffes, the Flatiron Building, a school
bus, etc. Here is how we'd translate this sentence using our two categories:
Some birds are things that are taller than President Obama.
Again, although this sentence sounds strange in English, it has the same form as the categorical form, some S are P, and it allows us to clearly see what the two categories are. Below is the Venn diagram for this statement:
By convention, an asterisk on the Venn diagram means that there is at least one
thing in that category. By putting the asterisk in the intersection of the two
categories, we are saying that there is at least one thing that is a bird and is
taller than President Obama, which is exactly what our original sentence was
saying.
Finally, let's consider the statement, "some birds don't fly". How would we
translate this sentence to have the "some S are not P" form? The first step is to
get the descriptions of the two categories using either nouns or noun phrases.
The "S" term is easy; it is just "birds" again. But we have to be a bit more
careful with the "P" term, since its predicate contains a negation. We do not
want any of our categories to contain a negation. Rather, the negation is
contained in the form (i.e., the "not"). The category cannot be simply "fly" or
even "flies" since neither of these are a category of thing. We have to use our
trick of turning the predicate into a noun phrase, i.e., "things that fly". Given
these two category descriptions, we can then translate the sentence to have the
categorical form, some S are not P:
Some birds are not things that fly
Again, although the English sounds clunky here, it has the same form as the categorical form, some S are not P, and it allows us to clearly see what the two categories are. Below is the Venn diagram for this statement:
By convention, an asterisk on the Venn diagram means that there is at least one
thing in that category. By putting the asterisk inside the "birds" category, but
outside the "things that fly" category, we are representing that at least one
thing that is a bird isn't a thing that flies. This is exactly what our original
sentence was saying.
Translating categorical statements into their categorical form can by tricky. In
fact, it is probably one of the trickier things you'll do in formal logic. There is no
simple way of doing it other than asking yourself whether your translation
accurately captures the meaning of the original English sentence. Here is an
example of a tricky categorical statement:
Nobody loves me but my mother.
This is a categorical statement, but which of the four categorical forms does it
have? The first step is to ask what two categories are being referred to in this
sentence. Here are the two categories: "things that love me" and "things that
are my mother". Notice that the category couldn't just be "my mother" since
that isn't a category; it's a particular thing. Again, this sounds strange, but it is
important to remember that we are describing categories of things. The next
question is: what is this sentence saying is the relationship between these two
categories? Hint: it has to be one of the four categorical forms (since any
categorical statement can be translated into one of these four forms). The
sentence is saying that the only things that love me are things that are my mother. The categorical form of the statement is the "all S are P" form. Thus,
the sentence, translated into the correct categorical form would be:
All things that love me are things that are my mother.
We will end this section with one last example. Consider the following
categorical statement:
The baboon is a fearsome beast.
Which of the four categorical forms does this statement have? Although the
article "the," which often denotes particulars, may lead one to think that this is a
particular affirmative form (some S are P), it is actually a universal affirmative
form (all S are P). This English sentence has the sense of "baboons are fearsome
beasts" rather than of "that (particular) baboon is a fearsome beast". English is
strange, which is what makes translation one of the trickiest parts of logic. So,
the two categories are: "baboons" and "fearsome beasts". Notice that since
"fearsome beasts" is already a noun phrase, we don't have to add "things that
are..". to it. Using the two category descriptions, the translation into the "all S
are P" categorical form is thus:
All baboons are fearsome beasts.
In this section we have learned what categorical statement are, how to translate
categorical statements into one of the four categorical forms, and how to
construct Venn diagrams for each of the four categorical forms. The following
exercises will give you some practice with the translation part; in subsequent
sections we will learn how to use Venn diagrams as a formal method of
evaluating a certain class of arguments.
Source: Matthew J. Van Cleave
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 License.