Read this section for an introduction to formal logic. Formal logic gives us a framework for objective, logical evaluations of conclusions. It can help you make valid inferences for certain kinds of statements. This section will not go deeply into how to do this type of logic but rather explain why it is important and give some basic examples.
In chapter 1 we introduced the concept of validity and the informal test of
validity. According to that test, in order to determine whether an argument is
valid we ask whether we can imagine a scenario where the premises are true and
yet the conclusion is false. If we can, then the argument is invalid; if we can't
then the argument is valid. The informal test relies on our ability to imagine
certain kinds of scenarios as well as our understanding of the statements
involved in the argument. Because not everyone has the same powers of
imagination or the same understanding, this informal test of validity is neither
precise nor objective. For example, while one person may be able to imagine a
scenario in which the premises of an argument are true while the conclusion is
false, another person may be unable to imagine such a scenario. As a result, the
argument will be classified as invalid by the first individual, but valid by the
second individual. That is a problem because we would like our standard of
evaluation of arguments (i.e., validity) to be as precise and objective as possible,
and it seems that our informal test of validity is neither. It isn't precise because
the concept of being able to imagine x is not precise - what counts as imagining
x is not something that can be clearly specified. What are the precise success
conditions for having imagined a scenario where the premises are true and the
conclusion is false? But the informal test of validity also isn't objective since it is
possible that two different people who applied the imagination test correctly
could come to two different conclusions about whether the argument is valid.
As I noted before, this is partly because people's understanding of the
statements differ and partly because people have different powers of
imagination.
The goal of a formal method of evaluation is to eliminate any imprecision or lack
of objectivity in evaluating arguments. As we will see by the end of this chapter,
logicians have devised a number of formal techniques that accomplish this goal
for certain classes of arguments. What all of these formal techniques have in
common is that you can apply them without really having to understand the
meanings of the concepts used in the argument. Furthermore, you can apply
the formal techniques without having to utilize imagination at all. Thus, the
formal techniques we will survey in this chapter help address the lack of
precision and objectivity inherent in the informal test of validity. In general, a
formal method of evaluation is a method of evaluation of arguments that does
not require one to understand the meaning of the statements involved in the
argument. Although at this point this may sound like gibberish, after we have introduced the formal methods, you will understand what it means to evaluate
an argument without knowing what the statements of the argument mean. By
the end of this chapter, if not before, you will understand what it means to
evaluate an argument by its form, rather than its content.
However, I will give you a sense of what a formal method of evaluation is in a
very simple case right now, to give you a foretaste of what we will be doing in
this chapter. Suppose I tell you:
It is sunny and warm today.
This statement is a conjunction because it is a complex statement that is
asserting two things:
It is sunny today.
It is warm today.
These two statements are conjoined with an "and". So the conjunction is really
two statements that are conjoined by the "and". Thus, if I have told you that it
is both sunny and warm today, it follows logically that it is sunny today. Here is
that simple argument in standard form:
- It is sunny today and it is warm today.
- Therefore, it is sunny today. (from 1)
This is a valid inference that passes the informal test of validity. But we can also
see that the form of the inference is perfectly general because it would work
equally well for any conjunction, not just this one. This inference has a particular
form that we could state using placeholders for the statements, "it is sunny
today" and "it is warm today":
- A and B
- Therefore, A
We can see that any argument that had this form would be a valid argument.
For example, consider the statement:
Kant was a deontologist and a Pietist.
That statement is a conjunction of two statements that we can capture explicitly
in the first premise of the following argument:
- Kant was a deontologist and Kant was a Pietist.
- Therefore, Kant was a deontologist. (from 1)
Regardless of whether you know what the statements in the first premise mean,
we can still see that the inference is valid because the inference has the same
form that I just pointed out above. Thus, you may not know what "Kant" is (one
of the most famous German philosophers of the Enlightenment) or what a
"deontologist" or "Pietist" is, but you can still see that since these are
statements that form a conjunction, and since the inference made has a
particular form that is valid, this particular inference is valid. That is what it
means for an argument to be valid in virtue of its form. In the next section we
will delve into formal logic, which will involve learning a certain kind of
language. Don't worry: it won't be as hard as your French or Spanish class.
Source: Matthew J. Van Cleave
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 License.